This chapter is a collection of situations that are brought up as problems to be solved by various philosophers.
There are only three ways of completing a proof:
The circular argument, in which the proof of some proposition presupposes the truth of that very proposition
The regressive argument, in which each proof requires a further proof, ad infinitum
The dogmatic argument, which rests on accepted precepts which are merely asserted rather than defended
This is a dilemma for classical logic in particular; it could be addressed by introducing nonmonotonic logic (default and challenge). Some claims (e.g. first person observations) come with a default justification (which is not based on the justification of other claims). Yet it must be defended when challenged.
Original argument appearring in Chapters II and III of [1] (1893), and S.E.P. commentary here:
Bradley notes that there appears to be such a thing as ‘a lump of sugar’, and this thing appears to have qualities such as whiteness, sweetness, and hardness.
But what is this “thing” that bears properties?
On the one hand, it’s odd to assume that there is something to the lump of sugar beside its several qualities
So, postulating a property-less bearer of properties is incoherent.
On the other hand, he notes that the lump cannot merely be its qualities either, since the latter must somehow be united.
For Bradley, unity or “coexistence” of qualities presupposes relations.
But the ontology of relations is prone to the following infinite regress:
We postulate the relation \(C\) that relates properties \(A\) and \(B\)
We then need a relation to relate \(C\) to \(A\) (and to \(B\)).
An easy way to tell if someone saying \(P\) means \(\phi\) rather than \(\psi\) by some observable concept is to show them \(\phi\)’s (witness them say \(P\)) and \(\psi\)’s (and witness them not say \(P\)). Call this witnessing the distinction via dispositions of the \(P\)-speaker. Disjunctivitis is a thought experiment that says this is not a sufficient tool for us to distinguish \(\phi\)’s and \(\psi\)’s generally. This is a Kripkensteinian problem.
We’re worried about whether the word ‘porcupine’ really means porcupine, or whether it means porcupine or echidna. Because most of us porcupine users can’t tell porcupines from Australian echidnas. And, although everything I’ve ever seen in called a ‘porcupine’ was a porcupine, everything I’ve ever seen called a ‘porcupine’ was also a porcupine or echidna. And the question is, well, what what fact is it in virtue of which ‘porcupine’ means porcupine, and not porcupine or echidna?
You can’t tell it from my dispositions on the output side, and on the input side, though, it might have been equally true that they’ve all been porcupines they’ve also been porcupines or echidnas. (Furthermore, for all I know, they all happened to have been been male porcupines, in which case we have to worry that my word porcupine means male, porcupines and again, I can’t tell them from the female ones.
Solution from Sellars: the people who taught you the word porcupine, what pattern were they trying to inculcate in you? Was it to say ‘porcupine’ when confronted with a porcupine or echidna? This is a crucial piece of how the noise ‘porcupine’ coming out of my mouth means porcupine.
A problem metaethical theories belonging that are emotivist/ expressivist. Also sometimes called the embedding problem.
Theories in the noncognitivist tradition share the view that the distinctive meaning of moral words does not concern what they are about, and it either does not require or is not exhausted by any answer to what makes moral sentences true. For example, according to A. J. Ayer, the word ‘wrong’ works more like ‘dammit’ than like ‘common’, so that ‘stealing money is wrong’ means something more like, ‘dammit, stealing money!’ than like ‘stealing money is common’. But standard ways of understanding the meanings of complex sentences, and of understanding the logical relationships between sentences, depend on an answer to what those sentences are about, or what would make them true. So noncognitivists need a different, nonstandard, answer to how the meanings of simple sentences give rise to the meanings of complex sentences. The problem of how to do so, and of whether it can even be done, has come to be known as the Frege-Geach problem.
To follow a rule (e.g. ‘under circumstances \(C\), do \(A\)’, or ‘Whenever you see a cat, raise your hand’), we have to understand the concepts that are involved within (i.e. \(C\) or cat, or raising one’s hand).
However, to grasp a concept (such that the original rule can be followed) requires a further rule.
Put another way, because rules have many interpretations, for any rule \(R\) we need another rule which tells us whether or not we correctly applied \(R\).
If a law says ‘Every man must serve in the army’, then it will naturally require a law for determining who qualifies as ‘man’. That law (say, ‘A man is whatever the scientific experts label with the word man’) will naturally require a law for determining who qualifies as ‘scientific expert’… the regress will continue if we try to adjudicate ‘scientific expert’ with another rule.
This skepticism about rules is really a skepticism about a certain theory of meaning (i.e. semantic skepticism).
There are many flavors, but consider the brain in a vat thought experiment:
You are sleeping one night, when the scientist takes out your brain, puts it in a vat, and connects its neurons to a machine that gives/receives electrical inputs such that the brain activity is identical to certain possible real life scenarios if the brain was still in the body.
The brain in the vat could be having the same experiences I am having right now, so why can I be confident that I am not a brain in a vat?
It seems there is no problem thinking about what triangles and white things are, but what of triangularity and whiteness?
This seems to be an instance of the tooth pain issue. Noun-ness was for ordinary objects (with obvious ontological status) in an earlier game, but our creativity with language led us to nounify many other words, leading to ‘objects’ with unclear ontological status.
Realism asserts that universals are real things, that triangularity does refer to something in the world, although perhaps some metaphysical realm.
Plato is an example.
Berkeley rejected Locke’s view of abstract ideas on empiricist grounds. For him triangularity is just a name that refers to all triangles, rather than referring to something in particular.
There are no abstract ideas, just particulars.
One can accept that universals refer to things in the world but be clear that they are mental things (concepts). Locke is an example.
By Lewis Caroll in 1895. [2]
The Tortoise assumes a proposition \(p\) and a material conditional \(p \implies q\).
The exact \(p\) and \(q\) aren’t important to the moral of the story, though it’s something like “If \(A=B\) and \(B=C\) (\(p\)), then \(A=C\) (\(q\))”
The Tortoise is playing a game: I’ll do anything you tell me to do, so long as you make explicit the rule you’re asking me to follow.
Achilles tries to convince the Tortoise to accept \(q\).
He says that logic obliges you to acknowledge \(q\) in this case.
The Tortoise is willing to go along with this but demands that this rule be made explicit:
Achilles adds an extra axiom: \(p \land (p \implies q) \implies q\).
Achilles says that, now, you really have to accept \(q\), given that you’re committed to:
\(p\)
\(p \implies q\)
\(p \land (p \implies q) \implies q\).
But the Tortoise notes that, if taking those three propositions and concluding \(q\) is really something logic obliges one to do, then it bears writing down:
\(p \land (p \implies q) \land (p \land (p \implies q)) \implies q\)
This can go ad infinitum; the Tortoise wins.
The most influential pragmatist work in the philosophy of logic.
The lesson:
in any particular case, you can substitute a rule (that tells you you can go from this to that) with an axiom.
But there have got to be some moves you can make without having to explicitly license them by a principle.
I.e. you’ve got to distinguish between 1.) premises from which to reason 2.) principles in accordance with which to reason.
This teaches an un-get-over-able lesson about the necessity for an implicit practical background of making some moves that are just okay. Things that would be put in a logical system, not in the forms of axioms, but in the form of rules.
(This is from one of his Sellars lectures)
This seems analogous to descriptivism vs expressivism.
It illustrates what we lose when we reduce all discourse to descriptive discourse. When we choose our definitions such that natural laws are facts in the world, just like any other ordinary empirical fact, we lose both:
Their role in reasoning
A story for our knowledge/justification of them.
The story shows how treating a rule as a fact strips it of its normative force. It is the problem of conflating description in the narrow sense with description in the wider sense: see here.
The last line of this commentary makes me think this can also be used to counter some forms of radical skepticism, i.e. to recover an air of dignity to making working assumptions.
Philosophical ‘situations’ is a very ambiguous category of anecdotes. They’re descriptions of the world (hypothetical or realistic) that can be seen as problems in their own right, or counter-examples to some commonplace theories, or evidence in favor of a particular theory, etc.
I wander in from a different culture, into an auction house
There, the significance of waving your hand is bidding the next amount on whatever is being auctioned.
But all I know of the local customs is that waving usually is a greeting for people.
So, I go in there and greet my friend by waving.
I’m unaware that, in this context, doing that has the significance of bidding $500 for that armoire.
Now, if, as a matter of fact, I’m held responsible there (“You’ve implicitly accepted these rules by going into the auction house!”), then I’ve actually bid. That’s what I’ve done.
Even though I didn’t intend to do that, I didn’t mean to do that. But I produced a performance that has that significance.
A parallel story:
In Napoleon era, England, they needed sailors
This was a terrible life; nobody would want to do this.
Yet the law was that one had to voluntarily join Her Majesty’s Navy.
Because people were illiterate, taking the Queen’s shilling from a duly authorized representative of Her Majesty’s Government showed that you had voluntarily joined the service
If you did that, you had joined the Navy. You had committed yourself.
So, they’d go to the bars and wait until somebody was drunk and out of money to say, “Like a shilling for another drink, mate?”
They weren’t wearing the uniform or anything that shows that they were the duly authorized representatives
But they had the papers to show they were. You couldn’t deny there were all these witnesses that you took the shilling from this person.
This is an equivalent of having bid on the armoire: the law was, if you performed that act, regardless of intention, that counted as committing yourself.
An empirical phenomenon: when a foraging bee discovers a supply of food, it returns to the hive and does a waggle dance. The rest of the hive then flies out in a certain direction and distance, locating the food. In some sense, the bee communicates the information of the food supply to the hive.
What’s philosophically interesting about this?
How do we talk about what the bee is doing?
Is the bee ‘speaking a language’? Is the bee saying that ‘food is located in this direction’?
Can’t we explain why a particular bee on one occasion does that by invoking the pattern that it’s an instance of?
What would it mean to say of a bee returning from a food source that it’s turnings and wiggling has occurred because they’re part of a complete dance?
This is related to distinction of pattern governed vs rule obeying behavior.[3] Ruth Milliken, Sellars’ student, devotes her career to this, developing the field of teleosemantics and writing about it in Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories.[4]
A simpler example: imagine that beavers slap their tail when there’s danger, and beavers flee when they hear another beaver slap its tail.
The idea of teleosemantics is an evolutionary sort of semantics.
Acknowledge language use is normative (make distinction between correct and incorrect use).
You have to draw the distinction in the way that’s compatible with any degree of badness of the participants actually following the rules.
We look at a reproductive family, the normal explanation (a tehcnial term) of tail slapping is that, in the evolutionary history, lives were saved by it.
When the explanation of the persistence of tail slapping turns on particular events in the past where things worked well that way (expressed in terms of counterfactuals - no tail slap, then species dies out), then we can say its part of the proper function (technical term) to perform that behavior.
This solves some puzzle cases: it allows us to say the proper function of sperm is to fertilize eggs even if a vanishingly small fraction of them actually do (because if they hadn’t fertilized eggs in the past, there wouldn’t be sperm now).
Well, this is the form of explanation for semantics in general. Because the same thing can happen when the reproductive families are uses of words.
You can explain why we use the word ‘Aristotle’, as we do, if has having a proper function of, in the end, referring to Aristotle, because if people in the past had not used it, in particular ways, we wouldn’t be using it today.
And similarly, for predicates, and so on.
These are not biological norms. But we can understand words as having proper functions in the same sense in which even in the merely biological case, we can understand things as having proper functions. And we can understand them as having proper signaling functions.
So, there’s a proper function for producing these things and a proper function for receiving them.
There, the analogy of the of the tail slaps is a good one.
In order to understand semantic content, we don’t need to use any principles of explanation that aren’t already intelligible.
This is related to the problem of: suppose you follow a rule. You use a representation of that rule to train the next generation to follow the rule. How do we know that the same rule is being passed on? Isn’t it like a game of telephone, given the ambiguity of following rules (gerrymandering problem - you have a rule in your head and punish me for lifting the glass of water, but I interpret this as punishment for lifting my arm or one of a million other possible explanations). Brandom’s response:
Well, maybe so and maybe it a given rule isn’t as stable as we think. I mean, it’s only if it had enough coherence and enough stability, that we’re here. (Anthropomorphic principle). And when Wittgenstein harps on this, you know, unless as a matter of fact, we tended to go on the same way when trained the same way, to a remarkable extent, we wouldn’t get a language game off the ground.
I should mention that this gerrymandering issue is what was wrong with classical behaviorism from an empirical point of view. 1 Remember, the stimulus and response were supposed to be objective features of the critters you were looking at. So that the behavioral scientist modeled on the natural scientist, her own conceptual scheme was not supposed to be involved in characterizing the behavior of these critters. But if you ask sort of classical studies, so I take the rat, and set him down four steps away from the bar, and train him, then if he walks four steps forward and presses down on the bar, he’ll get a rat yummy. And that stimulus, let’s say, the light goes on, walks, four steps, pushes down on the bar gets a rat yummy. We indoctrinate him with that, conditioned learning, he can do that. And now we ask the behavioral scientist. And now if I put in eight steps away from the bar, what do you predict he’s going to do? Is he going to go four steps forward and move his paw up and down? Is that the behavior that has been associated with the stimulus? Or would you predict that he’ll go eight steps forward and press down on the bar. That is, the right description is that he’ll go from where he is to the bar and press on the bar? Well, the minute you think about this, you realize that we can gerrymander, what he was taught, there are many descriptions, that that are available to us for what he was taught. And in fact, no one who works with the animals would expect him to move four steps forward, and not be pressing on the bar. But why is that? Is that something that you without importing any understanding of this are objectively reading off of the situation? Or have you, in fact, all along been importing, your characterization of what the regularity is that you are, that you’re characterizing? This is actually empirical as well a methodological problem. What is the prediction that you’re supposed to make at this point? And how do you justify the one rather than rather than the other by your methodological lights?
From: [5]:
A mother lets me watch her kids and says to me: Show the children a game. When she returns, she sees me teaching them to gamble with dice. She angrily exclaims I didn’t mean that sort of game! Must the exclusion of the game with dice have come before his mind when he gave me the order?
It’s true that she did mean not that sort of game. but she need not have had the conscious thought at the time of the request. Somehow her request made a normative division of proper responses.
If you find this puzzling that, nonetheless, what you did was an inappropriate response to her request, then you are trapped in a possibly Cartesian trap. You’re missing what distinguishes a sign from a piece of wood.
A common metaphor used to critize someone’s inquiry:
One night, a drunk man is searching on the ground under a streetlight. An officer approaches and asks “What are you looking for?”
“My keys.”
They look together for a while until the officer asks, “Are you sure you dropped your keys here?”
The man replies, “No, over there” and points to a dark patch far from the streetlight.
“Why in God’s name are you looking here, then?”
“Because there’s no light over there.”
Montaigne is impressed that his dog, when chasing a rabbit and coming to a fork, runs a little way down one of the paths and smells no rabbit, then immediately runs down the other fork of the path without stopping to smell to check if the rabbit went that way. [6]
The dog is acting in accordance with the disjunctive syllogism. Do we say that the dog understands disjunction?
We can sometimes underestimate the generativity of language, it’s radical novelty. Consider something as easy to understand as “For the picnic today, I hope you packed all the sandwiches we made last night and the baseball gear.”
Almost every sequence of words uttered by an adult native speaker is radically novel. Not just in the sense that that speaker has never produced or heard that sequence of words, but in the sense that no one ever has.
Example from Charles Travis [7] (Pragmatics, pg 97): - Maple trees have red leaves naturally, but Pia paints them green. - One day, a decorator asks her if she has any green leaves for her display, and Pia answers yes. - Another day, a chemist asks her if she has any green leaves for her experiment on green leaf chemistry, and Pia answers no. - In both cases, Pia answered truthfully.
The moral: any true sentence in some context has a context which would make its negation true.
We think it’s straightforward when a teacher points to a plate and says ‘plate’. However, one might argue the teacher has also pointed to:
the color of the plate
the shape of the plate
a piece of diningware
a plate or an elephant
a specific clump of atoms within the plate
etc.
We want it to be true that the teacher did, in fact, point to the plate (this is needed for us to understand how the students learn to respond to plates by saying ‘plate’). But we need an account.
What fact of the matter (the pointing, the thought inside the teacher’s head, the dispositions of the teacher) makes it the case that the teacher pointed to the plate?
This is related to the problem of disjunctivitis.
Pluto was first postulated in order to explain perturbations in the orbit of Neptune (by inference from Newton’s laws). At that point, Pluto was a purely theoretical object. When we got more telescopes and could observe Pluto ‘directly’. Overnight, Pluto’s status changed from theoretical object to observable object, but Pluto itself didn’t change.
From [8]:
A man has arrived at the grocery store to go shopping, but realizes he’s forgotten his shopping list. Unbenknownst to him, a spy is following him tasked with writing a list of everything that is put into the grocery cart. There are now two lists of groceries that have dual relationships to what is put into the cart:
The original shopping list:
If we want to know whether an item that is put into the cart is ‘correct’, we must look to the shopping list
This list has authority over what is put into the cart: the list sets the standards of correctness.
The spy’s list:
This, conversely, says nothing about what should be put into the cart.
If we want to know whether something written on the list is ‘correct’, we must look to the shopping cart.
The cart has authority over the spy’s list.
From [9]:
Imagine a community that talked about having gold or silver in one’s teeth
Later, the community extends that practice to talk about having pain in one’s teeth.
If, as a matter of contingent fact, the practitioners can learn to use the expression ‘in’ in the new way, building on (but adapting) the old, they will have fundamentally changed the meaning of ‘in’.
This can be seen by the fact that, in the old practice, it made sense to ask where the gold was before it was in one’s tooth, whereas in the new practice asking where the pain was before it was in the tooth can lead only to a distinctively philosophical kind of puzzlement.
From [10]:
A man serves in a WWII.
In a battle, he does something extremely heroicly, and lots of people see.
He then gets knocked down, loses his dog tags, rolls down a hill.
He wakes up later and has no memory of who he was until that point in his life.
He wanders off and is eventually found by another regiment who has no idea who he is.
He winds up in a hospital and makes his way back to America to go to college.
Meanwhile, his original troop assumes the heroic soldier died
(He was probably blown to smithereens, since no trace of him other than dog tags)
They start calling him The War Hero, and he’s awarded a posthumous medal of honor.
The solder gets interested in history and does a PhD.
He decides to writes about the battle he knows he was involved in (in some way).
He’s intruiged by the story of The War Hero and makes that his focus.
Soon, he knows everything there is to know about The War Hero in his life up until the battle.
One might say, casually, he knows more about The War Hero than The War Hero himself knew about himself.
This person has two distinct kinds of self knowledge:
- Knowledge of the person one happens to be
- This is the normal kind of self-knowledge
- "I am a graduate student in Berkekey"
- "I have amnesia and no memory of anything before the battle"
- Self-knowledge
- "The War Hero was born in Cinincatti on a cold day."
- "The War Hero was forced to wear shorts even during the winter."
- If it's true, why is it true? Judging by the truth conditions of the sentence, it's true because a certain person born in Cininitati and was fordced to wear short pants, etc.
Most of us have both types of knowledge, but because they so easily run together we conflate the two.
An American philosopher, born in 1950.
A lecture series taught in 2020. The course website is here.
Does ‘representation’ have a nature or a history?
Does it belong with “electrons” and “sulfur” or with “freedom” and “love”?
Brandom, being a Hegelian, thinks philosophy belongs in the latter category and proceeds to give a historical overview of ‘representation’.
Representation a modern concept.
Premodern theories understood relation between appearance and reality in terms of resemblance (sharing properties)
The rise of science made this untenable:
Copernicus: reality behind stationary Earth and revolving Sun is a revolving Earth and stationary Sun.
Galileo: effective strategies of understanding time as line lengths and acceleration as triangles … not easily understood in terms of shared properties.
Descartes invents representation with relationships between algebra (representation) and geometry (represented/reality).
Spinoza talks better about how Descartes used representation than Descartes himself. Spinoza saw Descartes’ philosophy as being understood in terms of his innovations of relating algebra to geometry.
“The order and connection of things is the same as the order and connection of ideas”
The properties of what is representing or represented are irrelevant, only that there is a mapping between the relations in each world.
If any things are known representationally, then some things must be known nonrepresentationally (to avoid infinite regress)
Representationalism gives rise to choice between epistemological skepticism vs foundationalism.
A Kantian insight: the real problem is semantic skepticism (can we really know something by representing it correctly?)
Kant says Descartes was right to think in terms of representation but that he didn’t distinguish two different kinds: picture like images/sensations vs sentence-like thoughts.
He saw both as different ends of a spectrum, while empiricists tried to reduce thoughts to pictures and rationalists vice-versa.
Spinoza’s interpretation of Descartes gives another view: within a representational picture, empiricists are atomists whereas rationalists are holists
Brandom’s interpretation using orders of explanation: empiricists treat representation as a primitive and infer reason-relations in terms of it. Rationalists treat reason relations as primitive, explain representational content in terms of inferential relations.
Rationalist Leibniz would have us understand the content of the map as the inferences that someone who treats it as a map could make about terrain facts (e.g. a river) from map-facts (wavy-blue line).
Sellars identifies both camps as descriptivists (to be conceptually contentful is just to describe / represent how things are).
Empiricists start with narrow postulate about what representing is and exclude a lot of genuinely contentful thought due to not meeting this standard (e.g. ethics, modality)
Rationalists take all our cognitively contentful expressions as therefore being part of the actual world, resulting in ontological extravagance (postulating objective values/universals/propositions/laws)
Sellars saw the Tractatus as teaching us how to get beyond this ideology with the case of logical vocabulary
Representation is a wider concept than description - Brandom thinks that Sellars’ anti-descriptivism is a form of anti-representationalism.
E.g. proper names represent without being descriptions, in Naming and Necessity.
Representation is a holistic conception, so rationalists were right about that (think: categories, relationships over properties)
Representation/description involve subjunctively robust relations between representings and representeds.
Considering the inferences of map facts to terrain facts, we also must accept that if the terrain were different, the map fact would be different.
Related to Fodor’s account of representation in terms of “one-way counterfactual dependencies of ‘horses’ on horses”.
Representation has a normative dimension
To treat representation as concerning what inferences we can make is a normative order.
Hegel appreciated this: to count as representing something is to be responsible to the represented thing (what is represented provides the normative standard for correctness of representing). What is represented has an authority over what is representing.
Declarativism: a relatively defensible representationalist position
Dual to “descriptivism” which too narrowly construes representation as description (which is too constricted a notion of representation).
This too broadly understands what all declarative sentences do in terms of fact-stating / truth-aptness (‘representation’ becomes too expansive). Expressivism is one way of negating this (by declaring “X is good”, one is commending rather than fact stating).
Intuition: the question of truth can be raised for whatever is expressed by declarative sentences.
Geach’s 1960 embedding argument: “If X is good, then …” a hallmark of fact-stating (if we had close the door or praise god, it wouldn’t make grammatical sense)
We can embed moral statements that 1st wave expressivists said were not fact-stating.
QUESTION: are there any grammatically declarative sentences which cannot be embedded? Would a counterexample have to be a non-truth-apt, declarative sentence?
Declarative sentences that may not fit into the fact-stating mold of “the frog is on the log”:
Logical (e.g. negative/conditional facts), modal (e.g. necessity), probabilistic, semantic (what expressions mean or represent), intentional (possibly about non-existent objects like golden mountains / round squares), normative, abstract / mathematical.
Are these all types of facts? Do they represent features of the world?
Rorty characterizes pragmatism as fundamentally anti-representationalist (Cheryl Misak strongly disagrees and considers Rorty to be a false heir of the tradition)
Representationalism is an ideology - that the meaning of thoughts/talk should be principally understood in terms of representational relations the thinkings/sayings stand in to what they (purport to) represent.
It’s a crippling ideology that must be rejected wholesale, no hope of redemption.
It’s synonymous with modern philosophy, so that must be jettisoned too.
Two sides of Wittgenstein:
Tractatus = representationalism (but providing the model for moving beyond it w/r/t logical vocabulary)
Logical tradition from Frege/Russell, operative paradigm of formal calculi for artificial symbolic languages.
Possible world semantics best distillation of its representational approach to meaning
Investigations = anti-representationalism.
Anthropological tradition focuses on natural languages, in tradition of Dewey. Rorty claims Heidegger also in this tradition, which both sides (pragmatists and Heidegger allies) don’t like. Focus is not on meaning but on use.
Arguments:
(Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature) - representational in semantics leads to an unproductive oscillation in epistemology between skepticism and foundationalism
Pragmatism about norms
antiauthoritarianism argument (completing the emancipatory project of the Enlightenment)
Simon Blackburn applies local expressivism in order to get a distinctive flavor of antirepresentationalism.
“Fact stating discourse” can be regarded as crucially important without dismissing all other kinds of discourse as defective/reducible.
Expressivism is a broad family of views claiming some areas of discourse are ‘in the business’ of giving expression to sentiments/commitments/non-cognitive or non-representational mental states or attitudes.
Huw Price synthesizes these two strands of anti-representationalism.
Agrees with Rorty that representation should never be used to do substantial explanatory work. They are global antirepresentationalists, which is a radical position currently.
He unites original German global expressivism (beginning with Herder) with second wave local expressivism of Blackburn and Gibbard.
rejects local expressivism, which requires us to distinguish vocabularies which should be given representational analyses or not - however he argues this cannot be done without embracing declarativism which the local expressivists wanted to avoid.
He reads into later Wittgenstein to unite global expressivism with Rorty
involves distinction between traditional object naturalism (how can we reduce facts in terms of natural science truth-makers) and the pragmatist’s subject naturalism (only seeks that reduction for the discursive practices consisting of use of language).
Brandom argues this global antirepresentationalism goes too far - prioritizing use over meaning (i.e. semantics answers to pragmatics) does not rule out representational/descriptivist accounts of vocabularies in general.
Disagrees with Pryce’s argument that local expressivism is not possible.
Neokantianism vs socialized/historicized/naturalized alternative.
Struggle between two camps in the 19th century, which is then re-enacted in the 20th century
Neokantianism (Marburg / Freiburg to CI Lewis and Carnap). Philosophy has sovereign authority.
Idea originates with Plato, but Descartes/Kant/representationalism are modern versions.
Neohegelianism (Hegel socialized philosophy, Marx naturalized it). Philosophy brought ‘down to Earth’.
Bertrand Russell and Husserl found things for philosophy to be apodictic about. Basis of Rorty’s ‘astonishing’ claim that analytic philosophy is just a phase of neokantianism
Russell and those downstream don’t think of themselves this way.
But they share the idea that philosophy of language is “first philosophy” and that linguistically-inflected philosophy of mind could advance our notions of epistemology and general theory of representation.
Shared emphasis on understanding language semantically, distinct from understanding knowledge epistemologically.
Husserl subject to Sellars’ critique of the Myth of the Given, Russell subject to Quine’s critique of Myth of the Museum. (Carnap subject to both).
“Uncritical semantics is the myth of a museum in which the exhibits are meanings and the words are labels. To switch languages is to change the labels”. Against the museum myth, Quine argues here for the indeterminacy of “meaning” and translation.
These are both (semantic) holist arguments.
Rorty regards the pragmatist/holist Quine+Sellars rebuttals as bringing us back to Dewey’s socialized/historicized/naturalized philosophy, with the 20th century being a pointless, big detour (despite increase in technical advances in logic/language).
Two kinds of privileged representations: sense impressions and representings of meaning (meanings thought representationally instead of functionally)
Rorty sees common genus to analytic meaning-articulating claims and the sensory given: privileged representations
common origin: role as infinite regress stoppers for the two types of representations, sensuous intuitions and inference-licensing concepts, that Kant distinguished (which each have these relations of privilege/authority).
Agrippan trilema of alternatives to skepticism
justification always in reference to other claims which require justification (this can be circular or infinite regress) OR there are unjustified justifiers / foundations.
If we have foundations, we need two kinds of regress stoppers:
premises that have authority
inferential transitions that have authority
These are not the same as premises, c.f. Tortoise and the Hare
That the “privileged representations” are authoritative and immediate, a kind of atomism follows from their privilege.
In order to play their epistemically-privileged roles, the regress stoppers must be semantically-privileged insofar as not depending on any collateral epistemic commitments.
Quine and Sellars’ critiques render such semantic privilege as practically unintelligible. A requirement that cannot be fulfilled.
Holist/pragmatic arguments of Sellars (against sense-givenness) and Quine (against meaning-givenness) that connect epistemology and semantics.
Sellars in EPM
Locke got confused by conflating the causation of a belief from its justification.
Sense data may be causally prerequisite to knowledge, but it cannot justify belief (it’s not conceptually contentful, in the sense of standing in reason relations of implication/justification).
To stand in reason relations requires lots of other infrastructure, such that atomic sense data cannot do this on its own (this is a semantic holist argument)
How do we acquire knowledge in the semantic holist POV?
How to get into the game of giving and asking for reasons? “The light dawns slowly over the whole” We need to get good enough at making the ‘right’ moves (as judged by ‘competent speakers’ before counting as a ‘competent speaker’.
Quine in TDE
Target: analytic truths, e.g. “cats are mammals” supposedly not depending on any other commitments but rather immediately from the meanings of the words.
What is the practical difference between these truths and very general facts, such as “there have been black dogs”.
Duhem-Quine thesis: “it is impossible to test a scientific hypothesis in isolation, because an empirical test of the hypothesis requires one or more background assumptions”.
What inferences we are allowed to make depends on the whole of collateral beliefs we have.
The unit of meaning must be the web-of-belief rather than the concept or the sentence.
Fodor argues against this, considers mixing epistemology and semantics to be a big philosophical mistake initiated by Quine.
Is Rorty attacking a strawman? Empiricism / Epistemic foundationalism is not popular now:
“Default and challenge” structure a way of avoiding Agrippan trilemma.
Bayesianism sees all justification as comparative (never have to justify one’s prior commitments).
though the problem of semantics is still open if it is to not be representationalist
Naturalism + representationalism remains unchallenged.
picking an ontologically privileged base vocabulary
So Rorty and Pryce need to do one or both of:
Argue independently for pragmatism, then use that to attack representationalism without passing through foundationalism
Argue independently against representationalism and propose pragmatism as the best alternative approach
(From the discussion of truth as “what is best in the way of belief” as opposed to correspondence with reality):
How the combination of:
declarativism
blurring out all distinctions of kind of claimable
expressivism
a local expressivism about what one is doing in attributing truth—namely not describing the claimable, but endorsing it—
underwriting a global antirepresentationalism because of special properties of the vocabulary of truth
together underwrite a Jamesean understanding of truth-talk.
This role for an expressivist move in a pragmatist argument forges an important link between the first and the second halves of this course.
(From the discussion of representation):
What is really at stake in the battle between a representational model of the content of expressions and a pragmatist model is the best order of explanation (a way of thinking about conceptual priority) between representational relations and reason relations (of implication and incompatibility).
Davidson teaches us that and how taking reason relations as primary (the pragmatists says, because giving and assessing reasons, implicitly and practically appealing to justificatory reason relations, specifiable in a deontic normative vocabulary of “commitment” and “entitlement”’) holistically determines representational relations in top-down explanatory stories.
Representationalists are committed to atomistic objective usually causal relations (specifiable in an alethic modal vocabulary) determine reason relations.
Rorty takes for granted a distinction of Dewey:
Platonism | pragmatism |
---|---|
Principles | practices |
Theoria | phronesis |
Knowing that | knowing how |
End the | Continuing the conversation |
Platonists look for a principle or rule, something explicit or that could be made explicit, behind every implicit propriety of practice.
Pragmatists argue that explicit principles or theories float on a vast sea of implicit practical skills.
For example, a cobbler can make good shoes. The Platonist looks for what form is behind his mastery, what principle / mental representation makes it possible that the cobbler does that? The pragmatist treats the skill as prior to the principle.
Rorty sees representationalism as the distinctly modern form of Platonism as described above.
Kant is the avatar of this form of representationalism: representations and rules are two sides of the same coin. He puts principle over practice (opposed by Dewey, who was followed by Heidegger and Wittgenstein in this respect).
This is Rorty’s way of talking about language games. Or paradigms (in the Kuhnian sense - Kuhn was writing just down the hall from Rorty). Vocabularies are what we deploy in discursive practice.
He thinks is needed as a successor notion to the idea of languages and theories, which was rightfully taken apart by Quine’s Two Dogmas of Empiricism.
Examples, how big are they? - on the one hand, the vocabulary of 16th century theology - also, the vocabulary of modernity - where that’s presumably an autonomous discursive practice
Philosophers think that they are debating about what is true in a given vocabulary when really their question is better framed as trying to pick the right vocabulary (important to realize this, since it changes how we compare arguments).
This point appears to be accepting the Carnappian distinction of theory and
Rorty makes fun of representational realists as being committed to the idea that there is a thing such as “nature’s own language” / “nature’s own vocabulary”
He sees Lewis as committed to this as the language which determines what the ‘natural properties’ are.
Rorty doesn’t draw a line between speaking in a vocabulary and changing your vocabulary (he thinks almost all speech acts change it).
Duhem point: if we acknowledge that your meanings at least partially determine what inferences are good. What follows a given sentence depends on what auxiliary hypotheses you’re allowed to use as collateral premises for
We can see what else you’re committed to has an effect on that sentence, given the meaning of that sentence is characterized by its inferential relations.
In mature sciences a lot of work is taken to allow for discourse to proceed as if the vocabulary were fixed
The discursive equivalent of “clean rooms”, maintained through heroic social disciplinary measures
This is for mature sciencies: if you think of the history of temperature, every single time a new way of measuring temperature was discovered, the concept changes
But it would be a serious mistake to take this extreme, artificial case to be the paradigm on the basis of which we understand the use of language in general. (Here we might think of Heidegger on the effort it takes to precipitate Vorhandenheit out of Zuhandenheit.
Rorty says: “On the pragmatist account, a criterion (what follows from the axioms, what the needle points to, what the statute says) is a criterion because some particular social practice needs to block the road of inquiry, halt the regress of interpretations, in order to get something done. So rigorous argumentation-the practice which is made-possible by agreement on criteria, on stopping-places - is no more generally desirable than blocking the road of inquiry is generally desirable. It is something which it is convenient to have if you can get it. if the purposes you are engaged in fulfilling can be specified pretty clearly in advance (e.g., finding out how an enzyme functions, preventing violence in the streets, proving theorems), then you can get it. If they are not (as in the search for a just society, the resolution of a moral dilemma, the choice of a symbol of ultimate concern, the quest for a”postmodernist” sensibility), then you probably cannot, and you should not try for it. The philosopher will not want to beg the question between these various descriptions in advance.”
The generation of new vocabularies.
This is the essence of discursive practice, is to be committed to a view of conversation as something to be continued.
But one can do other things with vocabularies than use them to describe. So “redescription,” though evocative, might be replaced by “recharacterization,” or “reconceptualization.”
“Pragmatists follow Plato in striving for an escape from conversation to something atemporal which lies in the background of all possible conversations”
Conversation is about redescribing our vocabulary as much as using it. It is the process that produces redescriptions.
Quantifying over all possible vocabularies is a temptation and something you would only attempt to do if you are trying to end all conversation. This is a fundamental mistake. - This is something the early Wittgenstein did in the Tractatus - He then learned not to do this. It’s related to his later view that language is a motley. - Dummett interpretation of Wittgenstein: - Wittgenstein would think that if there were any use for a philosophical notion of meaning, the point of having a notion of meaning would be to codify proprieties of use. - But there is no limit of things one can use language for, so we cannot systematically find all meanings of all expressions. - Wittgentstein tool analogy: - you would think that you could describe the different ways of using things in terms of what you do with them in the way you could tools, so that you could think of hammer and nails, screw and screwdriver, glue and glue brush, all his ways of attaching things to one another. And that would be a sort of common function that they could perform - Early W. thought ‘Yes, representation is like that. That’s what language is for’ - What about a wrench What about the pencil that the carpenter uses, or the level that the carpenter uses, or the tool belt or tool chest? Or the set of plans that they’re using? - All these are functioning differently, and there isn’t going to be a systematic way of saying all the different kinds of tools that you could have - Classic Wittgensteinian anecdotes turn on the malleability of language. (tooth example) - The metaphyiscal puzzle comes from having a STATIC, totalizing pictures of language rather than accepting it as a motley that evolves whenever you use it. - We carefully design mature natural science and math to not have this happen, but this should not be a model for how our language works. - This is why Wittgenstein is a semantic nihilist, he doesn’t think there are actually meanings. The plasticisty of language makes this impossible.
Rorty has another term that is part of the constellation that starts with “vocabulary” and includes “redescription” and “conversation.” It is “coping.” It is his generic term for what we do with vocabularies, generally. It is in terms of success at coping that we are able sometimes to assess and compare vocabularies as better and worse. In that regard, it plays a role analogous to the notion of accuracy of representation, that Rorty wants to persuade us to discard as specifying the dimension along which arbitrary vocabularies can be assessed as better or worse.
It is crucial to this notion of coping that standards for it are rigorously internal to the vocabularies being assessed.
Different kinds of facts are identified individuated by the vocabularies we use to state them. (e.g. Physical Facts, normative facts, nautical facts,…)
Rorty concludes if it doesn’t make sense to quantify over all possible vocabularies, then it doesn’t make sense to quantify over all possible facts (a new vocabulary is going to make it possible to state new facts)
Rorty rejects the distinction of objective and subjective facts.
(Stopped taking notes at 1:11, pg 6 of Brandom’s presentation notes)
Is there a bifurcation in ordinary empirical description vocabulary vs vocabularies where there isn’t a good correspondence between parts of the sentence and parts of the world? -E.g. “Jupiter has moons” vs “The universe is infinite” and “Love is the only law”
Representationalists can either 1.) postulate objects represented by the latter claims (e.g. love) or 2.) consider such sentences that don’t fit the representational mould as defective/inferior.
These latter claims definitely have a meaning though, as observable by the reason relations they stand in.
Brandom claims that the representationalism-vs.-antirepresentationalism issue is distinct from the realism vs antirealism one, because the latter issue arises only for representationalists.
Is “coping” talk just an evolutionary biology / memetic thing?
This ‘reductionist’ interpretation is not true for Rorty:
Language is not a tool, as Dewey would have it, though it’s a nice metaphor for some purposes, it can be stretched too far:
Tool requires a common purpose that you can compare different tools for (e.g. nails / glue / screws all are tools for sticking wood blocks together)
But we cannot formulate the goal of language without already having language (we don’t have access to “nature’s true language” to do this, either).
Thus the meaning coping must be within to some vocabulary.
Brandom summarizing Wittgenstein: ‘Meaning’ is a theoretical object-kind, postulated to codify proprieties of practice
it is no truer that: - “atoms are what they are because we use ‘atom’ as we do” - than that “we use ‘atom’ as we do because atoms are as they are.” - Both of these claims, the antirepresentationlist says, are entirely empty. - Both are pseudo-explanations. - It is particularly important that the antirepresentationalist insist that the latter claim is a pseudo-explanation.
The most general lesson of the discussion of Davidson is that the overall collision is between
the intrinsically holistic demands of reason-relations, understood in interpretivist terms by Davidson, and (also) in social-practical terms by Rorty,
Interpretism: to say someone is a believer is to invoke the possibility of interpreting their beliefs and actions together (in a way that maps onto our own beliefs)
While having a conversation with someone is how you learn what they mean by X, the fact you can have a conversation is what it means for them to mean something by X.
To say that someone believes something is to claim we can have a conversation with them.
and the claims representational relations determined independently of social practices of giving and assessing reasons, for instance (and paradigmatically) by objective, causal relations describable in alethic modal terms
Davidson is happy to impute extensions (referents) as an intermediate stage of interpretation. But he insists that the process be top-down, starting from reason-relations to assignments of referents.
Davidson’s big contribution:
flipping Tarski’s theory of truth:
Tarski: if you take meanings fixed, I can give you a recursive theory of which statements are truth.
Flipped: You can take ‘meanings’ to be the truth conditions (of all of the language). The starting point is the reason relations, and from those we derive the meanings.
We can argue about which order of explanation is better. Bottom up vs top down.
Bad theories
E.g. witches, phlogiston
We often find ourselves saying “Hard to say whether they’re talking about real things but are wrong about most of them or not talking about real things”
To what degree do ‘witch’ and ‘phlogiston’ refer?
It’s a matter of degree and a pragmatic decision.
So any theory that has as a consequence that there is a precise line between reference or non-reference is wrong.
Robert Brandom taught a recorded graduate seminar on Wilfred Sellars twice, in 2009 and and 2019. Notes on the recordings of these lectures are collected here.
The first of many lectures by Robert Brandom on Wilfred Sellars, delivered on September 2, 2009. It mainly talks about some ideas of Kant that influenced Sellars and introduces Sellars through a long series of quotes.
Kant was not in favor within analytic philosophy when Sellars began, due to Kant’s connection to Hegel2. However, this is ironic because Kant is incredibly analytical and science-driven.
Three ideas of Kant that mattered to Sellars:
Kant’s normative understanding of discursive practice3
How do we understand the difference between concept-using, sapient beings from mere responders to the natural environment? Here are two possible ways to think of it:
\(O\): An ontological distintion: knowers are an actually different kind of thing (perhaps there is a presence of ‘mind stuff’ or ‘spirit stuff’).
\(D\): A deontological distinction: we treat knowers differently from objects. There are things that the agents are in a distinctive sense responsible for 4.
Both sides treat \(D\) as true, but Team \(O\) furthermore believes \(O\) is true and that the order of explanation is \(O \implies D\). However, Team \(D\) takes \(D\) as essential and needs not make any claim about ontology.
Downstream of this are many of Kant’s innovations.
The minimum unit of awareness/experience is the judgment
this comes from taking \(D\) to be fundmental: it is the smallest thing we can be held responsible for
Everything else (particular concepts like Fido the dog, universal concepts like triangularity, logical concepts) has to be understood in terms of the function it plays with respect to judgment.
The subjective form of judgment (the “I think…” that can accompany all judgments)
Because it can accompany all representations, this is the emptiest form of judgment.
The mark of “who is responsible for the judgment”.
To say “I think it is raining now.” is to emphasize that I am responsible (e.g. subject to criticism if you go outside and don’t get wet).
The objective form of judgment (the “\(x\) is …” or “\(x\) = …” for some object \(x\)).
Mark of what you’ve made yourself responsible to.
When saying “That stone is 50 pounds.”, the stone has a certain authority over me (one looks to the stone to see whether I am right or wrong; it sets the standards of correctness). See the shopping list scenario.
Rousseau said “Obedience to a law that one has laid oneself is freedom.”
Kant turned this around to distinguish constraint by norms from constraint by power.
In addition to concepts whose principle expressive job is to describe/explain empirical goings-on, there are concepts whose principle expressive job it is to make explicit the framework that makes description possible.
These are known a priori framework-explicating concepts.
This is Kant’s response to Hume, for how we can understand the modal force of laws in virtue of their non-modal description.
The answer is in the description framework itself.
The fact that there are necessarily relations that concepts have among another makes description possible (a concept being contentful at all requires it to have some necessary relations to other concepts).
What Sellars means by ‘ushering philosphy from its Humean phase to its Kantian phase’ is putting categories front and center.
Trying to describe the modal structure of the world or describe the space of possible worlds is to try to assimilate modal language into descriptivism, rather than seeing them as playing a different expressive role
Sellars saw Kant as putting this other option on the table.
A difference between Humean thinking and Kantian thinking: for Kant, laws of nature are not ‘super-facts’ - they are not ‘describing the world’. Rather, they make explicit a rule of inference.
Another Kantian idea: the distinction between phenomena and noumena:
Kant radicalized the distinction between:
primary qualities (properties that are truly there)
secondary qualities (properties that are due to us).
He challenges us to divide the labor:
what features is the world responsible for?
what features are we responsible for?
E.g. the fact our theories are expressed in German/English
This distinction lives in Sellars as the difference between:
the world in the narrow sense
the world in the wider sense
E.g. which includes norms that are only accessible from a participant’s perspective.
The lecture finishes with some Sellars quotes on describing, explaining, and justifying.
He doesn’t begin with philosophically elaborated definition of describing, explaining, justifying. He takes these concepts as they come. He wants to do philosophy in a neutral / as close-to-practice way as possible.
This lecture was delivered on September 9, 2009. It coverse [3] and [11].
‘Mystery story’ style:
There’s a problem, and many competing potential explanations
These explanations engage each other dialectically
Only at the end would you learn the philosopher’s actual position
‘Journalistic’ style:
Tell them what you’re going to tell them
Tell them
Tell them what you told them
Sellars philosophical style is more the former.
Let an inference be a declaration of the form \(P \implies Q\)
There, \(P\) and \(Q\) are logical variables. We can also put other things in their place:
Non-logical vocabulary, e.g. red, cat, or it’s raining outside
Logical connectives: and, or, etc.
We want to distinguish certain inferences as material inferences, as distinct from logically-valid inferences.
Logically-valid inferences:
These are inferences that are true no matter what you plug in for the variables or substitute for the non-logical vocabulary.
E.g. \((A \land {\rm it's\ raining}) \lor C \implies (C \lor {\rm it's\ raining})\)
This is true, regardless of what we substitute for \(A\) and \(C\) (or swap “it’s raining” for anything, e.g. “I own two cats”).
Descriptive terms appear vacuously
Material inferences:
These can be changed from a good material inference into a bad one by substituting some nonlogical vocabulary for different nonlogical vocabulary
E.g. the material inference “\(a\) is red” \(\implies\) “\(a\) is colored” will become false if we replace ‘colored’ with ‘square’.
Descriptive terms appear essentially
Sellars has two good ideas associated with material inference:
There are some inferences that are good, not in virtue of their logical form.
Turn the above thought on its head and say: we can understand the content of these descriptive terms in terms of the materially good inferences they appear in (as premises or conclusions).
By this account, material proprieties of inference are more fundamental than / conceptually prior to logical validity. You have to start with the notion of a good inference in order to understand what a logically good inference is.
Aside: It took a while in the 20th century to realize that logic was not about logical truth but rather about validity of inference. In classical logic can you treat these interchangably, but not all (rough logics vs smooth logics - whether the consequence relation can be determined by the set of all theorems). Dummett has written about this issue.
What if we picked some other vocabulary (other than logical) to hold fixed? E.g. substituting non-theological vocabulary for non-theological vocabulary. “If justice is loved by the gods then justice is pious”. If no matter what we substitute for justice the inference is good, we might say the sentence is true in virtue of its theological form.
Philosophy of logic (See Quine’s and Putnam’s books both titled The Philosophy of Logic) has two classic questions:
a demarcation question: what makes something logical vocabulary?
Quine disallows second order quantifiers and the epilson of set theory, whereas Putnam allows them.
a correctness question: which logical consequence relation to use:
Classical? Intuitionistic? etc.
Sellars challenges this tradition (logical empiricism) by pointing out there is a concern conceptually prior in the order of explanation to philosophy of logic: materially good inferences.
A main argument of Inference and Meaning is that any language that makes essential use of non-logical, descriptive vocabulary must be understood as having that vocabulary standing in materially good (rather than just logically good) inferences.
A slogan for this: “Concepts as involving laws (and inconceivable without them)”
This is actually the title of an unintelligible essay by Sellars
Luckily the title is the thesis, and that much is intelligible
Sellars claims logical vocabulary has the expressive job of making explicit the material proprieties of inference that articulate the content of non-logical concepts.
More specifically than ‘logical’, he means alethic modal vocabulary: i.e. what’s necessary and what’s possible.
Historical note: Frege is more explicit about this point than Sellars: that you can use this to distinguish logical vocabulary.
The Montaigne example) highlights the difference between the capacity to use material inferences vs making that inference explicit:
Dan Dennett argues that we have to take animals as grasping modus ponens because they treat some inferences as good and others as bad
Sellars objects, saying that you could make explicit the practical capacity the animal has via a statement of disjunctive syllogism
But what is the surplus value of invoking that explicit expression? (Over simply describing what is the dog can do).
Talking about following rules very quickly gets into the regress of rules.
There have to be some practical moves you’re just allowed to make without them having to take the form of explicit premises (see Tortoise and Achilles).
Sellars touches upon this in Reflections on Language Games.
He talks about free/auxillary positions that you’re always allowed to occupy.
We could have the auxillary position \(\forall x, \psi(x)\vdash \phi(x)\) which would license us to move from a position \(\psi(a)\) to a position \(\phi(a)\), but we could also encode this with position for each possible move (\(\psi(a)\vdash \phi(a)\), \(\psi(b)\vdash\phi(b)\), ...).
He ways that we could imagine replacing positions with moves, but it’s not possible to imagine all moves being replaced with positions (‘a game without moves is Hamlet without the Prince of Denmark’).
Sellars is addressing tradition that wants some small set of explicit principles in accordance with which to reason. Any inference you think is good that isn’t derivable from that small set of principles (e.g. modus ponens) is actually an infamy (has some suppressed premises). This is early analytic philosophy’s embrace of the new logic. Sellar’s contrary view (radical at the time) is that actually the reasoning could be completely in order, just with material proprieties of reasoning. You can still give/ask for reasons and mean that \(p\), but what the logic does is give you meta-linguistic control to talk about what is a good inference and say that \(p \vdash q\) is a good inference.5
Example: \(A\vdash B\) where \(A\) is “she asked me to hand her the dish towel" and \(B\) is “I shall hand her the dish towel”. Traditional analytic philosophy will call this an infamy, since it does not explicitly state how her request engages my motivational structure. Sellars would want to say that this invocation of the desire makes explicit the endorsement of \(A \vdash B\) rather than referring to some item of the world.
Brandom: logic is the organ of semantic self-consciousness. The set of concepts that lets us bring our endorsement of some inferences as good/bad (this endorsement as something that reasons can be given or asked for) into the game of giving/asking for reasons.
Sellars complains about Carnap treating logical consequence as a syntactically definable relation between sentences. Just writing down the rules under a heading ‘rules’ instead of ‘axioms’ isn’t making explicit the normative force they have (it leaves out the rulishness - that a rule is a rule for doing something). This is a subtle point that doesn’t matter for many purposes, but Sellars believes it’s important if you want to understand what’s going on with reasoning. Again, strong connection between this point and Achilles and the Tortoise.
“There’s an important difference between logical / modal / normative predicates on the one hand, and such predicates as ‘red’ on the other.” There’s nothing to the formal except their role in reasoning, indeed, their role and make as meta linguistics sort of making explicit something about the ground level. For the latter, he wants to argue that these predicates too are meaningful insofar as their role in reasoning, but it’s less obvious.
“Red is a quality”. This conveys the same information as the syntactical sentence “Red is a one place predicate.” See quote. What you’re doing in asserting that premise from which to reason (couched in modal vocabulary) is endorsing a principle in accordance with which to reason (couched in normative vocabulary).
We cannot completely identify modal and normative statements with each other. Their relation is characterized by the say/convey distinction.
When I say "copper melts at 1084 degrees" one makes a claim that is true even if there were no reasoners (so it can’t be a claim directly about inferences being good). What it conveys is about inferences, not what it says. Likewise, I say “The sun is shining” while I convey “I believe the sun is shining.”
It might help to make progress toward understanding the say/convey distinction (which Sellars admits he’s not clear about) by distinguishing two flavors of inference:
semantic inference: good in virtue of the contents of the premises and the conclusion
pragmatic inference: good in virtue of what you’re doing in asserting the premises or the conclusion.
e.g. John says ‘your book is terrible’ and I infer that he’s mad at me
Geech embedding distinction between the two: we look at whether we’d endorse “My book is terrible, then John is mad at me". Because we wouldn’t, we know the inference is pragmatic.
Potential counterargument against Sellars: subjunctive conditionals are not making explicit proprieties of inference, but in fact are descriptions about possible worlds. To address this, we note there are separate issues. Firstly, there’s the question about whether it’s intelligible to have descriptive vocabulary in play in a context where there’s no counterfactual reasoning. E.g. Hume believes he understands empirical facts perfectly well (the cat is on the mat) but not statements about what’s possible and necessary. But Kant saw that this isn’t intelligble - you need to make a distinction about what’s possible with the cat and what’s not (it’s possible for the cat to not be on the mat, but not possible for it to be larger than the sun) or else there’s nothing you could say about the conctent of the concept of ‘cat’ that I’ve got (it would be just a label). The second issue is the codifiability of proprieties of material inference by logical vocabulary: whether a possible worlds analysis is incompatible with seeing subjunctive conditionals as making properties of inference explicit. Sellars would like to see a possible worlds analysis that matches up.
WARNING: Jotted down hastily, not yet cleaned up or fit for consumption.
Regulism (conceptual norms as a matter of explicit rules) vs regularism (norms in terms of actual regularities). These are identified with empiricist and rationalist approaches. (Kris: I also see prescriptivism and descriptivism in linguistics)
One purpose: “I shall have a chief my present purpose if I’ve made plausible the idea that an organism might come to play a language game, that is to move from position to position, the system of moves and positions, and to do it because of the system without having to obey rules, and hence without having to be playing a meta language game.” (Section 18)
He doesn’t explicitly mention Wittgenstein (who is a pariah in philosophy). (Other times he uses astrices to censor his name). Thinking about language in terms of rules is Kantian. His notion of norms was juridical/jurisprudential. A rule that enjoins the doing of an action A is a sentence in some language, which requires more rules to interpret (regress - how do we deal with it?). Kant identified this regress (A132/B171) - “judgment is a peculiar talent that can be practiced only and not taught”. Which is using distinction between things that can be shown (by examples) vs taught. Wittgenstein addresses this regress in the late 100’s of PI.
Rejecting mere conformity: If we just consider conforming to a rule rather than obeying a rule, there’s no regress, but we lose the normativity.
“[Mere conformity people] claim that it’s raining therefore the streets will be wet (when it isn’t an infamatic abridgement of a formally valid argument) is merely the manifestation of a tendency to expect to see the wet streets when one finds it’s raining. In this latter case, it’s a manifestation of a process which at best can only simulate inference, since it’s a habitual transition, and as such not governed by a principle or rule by reference to which can be characterized as valid or invalid. That Hume dignified the activation of an association with the phrase ‘causal inference’ is about a minor flaw, they continue, in an otherwise brilliant analysis. It should, however, be immediately pointed out that before one has a right to say that what Hume calls ‘causal inference’ really is an inference at all, but merely a habitual transition from one thought to another. And contrast that with in this context, the genuine logical inferences which are, one must pay the price of showing just how logical inference is something more than a mere habitual transition empiricists in the human tradition have rarely paid this price, a fact which is proved most unfortunate for the following reason. An examination of the history of the subject shows that those who have held that causal inference only simulates inference proper have been led to do so as a result of the conviction that if it were a genuine inference, the laws of nature, things that govern this would be discovered to us by pure reason. As they’re thinking of what’s a good inference having to be something that’s transparent merely by introspection in the way that the laws of logic are.” (him making point about distinction of real inferences and mere associations. )
No distinction between correct and incorrect can be made by purely pointing to regularity - as Wittgenstein pointed out, you’ll always find some regularity (there’s some elegant rule that generates the sequence, for any arbitrary sequence). This is also called ‘disjunctiv-itis’ or ‘gerrymandering objections’. After a debate between Dretsky and Fodor: we’re trying to see what makes the word porcupine mean porcupine. When ‘porcupine’ is used in an observational way, it’s typically in response to porcupines. So can we use that regularity to understand what ‘porcupine’ means? No, because of counterfactuals. If it happened that the porcupines we saw were almost always male, would the word mean male porcupine? Or if we look at dispositions, if they’re disposed to also call echidnas porcupines (that’s the disjunction), why not say that ‘porcupine’ means porcupine or echidna?
“what’s denied is the playing a game logically involves obedience to the rules of the game. And hence the ability to use the language to play the language game in which the rules are formulated.” (page 29) Need a sense of playing the game stronger than conforming but weaker than having the rules in mind.
Metaphysicus suggests why not a non-linguistic awareness of the rules? This is its own regress.
“We’ve tacitly accepted so far and the dialectic dichotomy between merely conforming to the rules and obey. But surely this is a false dichotomy. Is there something in between, for it required us to suppose that the only way in which a complex system of activity can be involved in the explanation of the occurrence of a particular act is by the agent explicitly envisaging the system and intending its realization. And that’s as much as to say that unless the agent conceives of the system, the conformity of his behavior to the system must be accidental. ” So what’s needed he’s saying, is going to be something that says, look, there’s an explanation of why he conforms to the rules. That invokes the rules, but it doesn’t invoke them by him being aware of them. One example of this is teleosemantics. See bee waggles.
The essential thing for Kant was a distinction between what was between acting according to a rule and acting according to a conception of a rule, or a representation (Vorstellung) of a rule. So, ordinary natural objects act according to rules, the laws of nature, but we act according to representations of rules / to conceptions of rules.
The explanation as to why I use the word ‘purple’ for purple things, the rule plays a crucial part even if it is not in my head. It is in the teachers’ heads (they’re already in the language and can conceive of rules). So the rule is causally antecedent to my behavior, so I can be following the rule (without regress).
Related quesiton addressed here: Classical Behaviorism
How is it that I can apply a concept according to norms, to invoke a pre-linguistic awareness of universals, that’s going to be a given. And the key thing is, because that pre-linguistic awareness is conceived of as providing reasons for me to do this. It’s not just that I’ve been trained to respond to some physiological thing by doing it (that would be okay. That could be part of the the real explanation, the pattern governed explanation). It’s that that pre-linguistic awareness provides reasons. And the claim is reasons are always making a move in a game that’s making the inferential move. And the question is: what determines the norms that govern that? Then we’re off on the on the regress, again, so we’ve got to have some story that doesn’t have that form. The form of the argument against the myth of the given. It’s the idea that the awareness that givenness provides something that can serve as a reason, but is itself not dependent on our having learned a language, having a conceptual scheme, and so on.
To do: understand language entry transitions and language exit transitions.
There is debate (but it should be more of a bigger deal, in Brandom’s opinion) about what are the minimal features needed for one to have a discursive language practice. Brandom views logical language as optional (though the expressive power would be incredibly stunted, you could still give and ask for reasons). MacDowell and Sellars think otherwise, that there can’t be discourse without a meta-language.
Sellars needs the notion of language to be something that evolves over time (rather than an instantaneous collection of rules) because we want the decision to make a material move to occur with in a language (one is not doing redescription in another language).
This lecture was delivered on September 16, 2009.
WARNING: Jotted down hastily, not yet cleaned up or fit for consumption.
Sellars wants to give us a naturalistic account of intentionality.
Logical behaviorism / philosophical behaviorism Def: the view that one can analyze without remainder intentional vocabulary / intentional concepts into purely behavior characterizations / dispositions to publicly observable behavior (specified in a non-intentional vocabulary).
Introduced in Empiricism in the Philosophy of Mind (9 years earlier), distinct from what he here calls logical behaviorism. Logical behaviorism refers to a view he attributes to Ryle. JB Watson and BF Skinner promoted this in psychology. Sellars never endorsed this because he saw this as being an application of instrumentalism in the philosophy of science.
Observable things, at least we know they exist. Theoretical things, we’ve got to make risky inferences to get to them. But we can also make observational mistakes. Not just “I thought it was a fox but it was a dog", but categorical observational mistakes. We can give some concept an observational role (e.g. declare that we can observe X’s) yet no X’s exist, i.e. no thing has such no thing with such circumstances of application and consequences of application. E.g. we can have a theory of acids. "Anything that’s sour is an acid. And anything that’s an acid will turn litmus paper red." Well, then we have observational access to acids. If we eventually find something that tastes sour that turns litmus paper blue, then it turns out there are no acids, even though we could observe them (or: had every reason to believe we could). Likewise: being a witch was observable (even though there are no such things).
The Plasticity of Mind is about bad theories incorporating observational practices, i.e. "What do you mean there are no K’s. I can see K’s, there’s one right there!"
So again, this is a response to someone saying we can distinguish theoretical from observable entities by pointing to the fact that we can make mistakes about whole categories of theoretical entities.
Just because our evidence for attributing mental states comes from behavior does not mean, unless you are an instrumentalist, that you have to be able to define intentional concepts in terms of behavior. (This doesn’t mean that the intentional states are less real, just that we aren’t in a position to observe anything but the behavior)
Digressions
Semantics is a field with instrumentalist vs theoretical realist views. Michael Dummett is instrumentalist by observing the fact that meaning something is only understood through verbal behavior and concluding that any theory of meaning must be definable in terms of behavior. (A theoretical realist might postulate meanings as theoretical entities to explain verbal behavior and say our access to meanings is inferential and, if they are good theories, then verbal behavior gives us inferential access to something (meanings) that exist.)
MacDowell and Sellars agree (and disagree with almost all others) that what you hear when someone talks to you is the words themselves, rather than hearing noises and (by some inferential process) constructing the words. You have to actually actively do some work to hear that mere noises. This is evidenced by how difficult it was to tell computers how to recognize a smile in a picture. (Some say it’s a contradiction to say that meanings are essentially normative yet, on the other hand, we sometimes can directly perceive them. But there’s nothing in principle unobservable about normative states of affairs - see Sellars’ criteria of observation below)
(Controversial) Criteria for observation:
You have the capacity to reliably and differentially respond to some normative state of affairs
You have to have the concept and which is a matter of inferential articulation and practical mastery of inferential proprieties, involving it. And then if you can hook the one up to the other, you’ve turned what was beforehand a theoretical concept for you into into the concept of an observable
Sellars wants to make sense of the notion of “language as a rule-governed enterprise" (as essentially involving norms). Sellars believes that if your account language doesn’t involven norms, you will be describing the vehicles by which we communicate, rather than what we’re saying/meaning.
Reminder that, due to the regress argument, that we need to broaden our notion of ‘rule’ from just explicit rules and need think of rules also as implicit in what we do. Sellars wants to better understand the relationship between implicit practical abilities and explicit representations of rules.
The question of whether meaning is a normative concept was brought to philosophical attention by Kripkenstein [12]. In present literature, Hattiangadi and Katherin Glüer have pushed back upon the idea that it is a normative concept, advanced by Brandom and MacDowell. Brandom feels it is because they haven’t learned lessons from Sellars, in particular thinking of norms purely in terms of explicit presecriptions and not making the distinction between ought-to-be’s and ought-to-do’s.
“You can define possibility in terms of not and necessity. You can define necessity in terms of not and possibility. I think it’s the beginning of wisdom to think of defining not in terms of the relationship between possibility and necessity, but I’m the only human being who thinks that."
Grice on non-natural meaning: reduces what a linguistic expression \(P\) means in terms of the meanings of thoughts and beliefs of those uttering \(P\). Sellars isn’t satisfied with this: the puzzling phenomena of meaning are common to both thought and language.
Sellars says “ought-to-be’s imply ought-to-do’s" but is not exact about what quantifier: all or some? Brandom thinks ‘some’ makes more sense, since there could be an ought-to-be requiring a state of affairs to change without telling us who has to do what to fix it (you need auxillary hypotheses to turn it into an ought-to-do). E.g. “all clocks should be in sync”.
With a trainer, someone with concepts/rules can condition language learners to shape their behavior (teach them ought-to-be’s). It’s important that it’s possible for the language enterprise get off the ground (i.e. without trainers). It’s possible for some sort of selection process to naturally reinforce ought-to-be’s (can be social but the conditioners need not be doing so intentionally).
We can deliberate making a distinction between ought-to-be’s in the context of humans vs nonliving/nonsentient beings (e.g. “plants ought to get enough water”). Ruth Millikan’s work relevant. Connects to the Aristotelian account.
Consider ought to be’s in the context of training animals: These rats ought to be in state \(\phi\) whenever \(\psi\).
Could be just for rats, qua rats
they ought to be eating when they’re hungry, or something like that
this could be something we want the rats to do
when they come to a branch in a maze, the rats go to the side that’s painted blue and not to the side that’s painted red.
That’s a regularity that ought to be not because we can read it off of the fundamental teleology of rats
The conformity of the rats in question to this rule does not require that they have a concept \(C\), e.g. of colors blue and red. We just require them to respond properly certain to differences emanating from \(C\). This doesn’t require even consciousness (photocells can respond differentially to colors).
“Recognitional capacity” gets systematically used in two fundamentally different senses (an ‘accordion word’)
reliable, differential response
applying a concept
Important for Sellars that following an ought-to-be requires only the former sense.
We should talk about learning a language as ‘coming into the language’ rather than ‘learning a language’. It’s more like the way one comes into a city. You come to be able to take part in an ongoing practice, as opposed to getting some intellectual insight.
Teaching the very young child to say ‘purple’ when showing her a purple lolipop is getting her to follow an ought-to-be just like the rat example. There is an ought-to-do for teachers of a language that they see to it that children produce the appropriate responses. This presupposes that the teachers do have a conceptual framework of ‘purple’ and of ‘vocalize‘ and what it is for an action to be called by a circumstance. The learner is not required to have any of these concepts. The ought-to-be is explicit in the teacher’s mind.
All of our evidence in science comes from empirical observation, so all of our concepts (and claims) must be translatable without remainder into observational vocabulary.
What warrant would there be for any conceptual excess beyond the language of our evidence?
There aren’t really any theoretical entities. We postulate them merely to characterize regularities of observable entities. Statements in the observational language are simply true or false, whereas statements in theoretical language are merely more or less useful.
This is a view that members of the Vienna Circle flirted with. A permanent temptation of the empiricist tradition.
The alternative is called theoretical realism. Sellars says this is a mistake (an example of "nothing-but-ism", along with emotivism in ethics), originating from thinking of the difference between observational vocabulary and theoretical vocabulary as an ontological difference in the objects referred to by those theories. But it’s not an ontological distinction, it’s a methodological distinction. Two different epistemic relations we can stand in to things that there are. Observable things are those that we come to know about by observation (non-inferential observation reports). Theoretical concepts are concepts that we can only be entitled to apply as a result of a process of inference. See Pluto example.
Ought to do’s | Ought to be’s |
---|---|
Rule of action | Rule of reflection |
If you’re in circumstances \(C\), do \(A\) | Pattern based judgment |
Conceptually articulated | Not necessarily conceptually articulated |
Rules of deliberation | Rule of assessment/criticism |
First personal | Third personal judgment of some behavior |
What’s appropriate for me to do? | Given what you did, was it appropriate? |
The person subject to the rule is the one following the rule | There may be no particular agent at all |
Examples? |
|
A distinction fundamental for both ‘must’ in the alethic and doxastic modal senses.
Sellars: You can’t understand either of these kinds of oughts without understanding both. In particular, if you try to do everything with ought-to-do’s:
one would fall into a kind of Cartesianism: we’d need to think of linguistic episodes as essentially the sort of thing brought about by an agent whose conceptualizing is not linguistic.
We’d be precluded from explaining what it means to have concepts in terms of the rules of the language. Ought to do’s have the form of “in circumstances \(C\), do \(A\)” - what language are \(C\) and \(A\) stated in? Regress of rules without ought-to-be’s.
This is important because natural way to think of rules is exlusively in terms of Ought to Do (Sellars himself advocated this earlier: “A rule is always a rule for doing something"[3]).
There is also an analogous distinction involving permission, rather than obligation.
You can’t understand what it is for somebody to be saying (and therefore thinking something) apart from the way they’re treated by some community. That’s a sense dependence: you can’t understand the one without the other.
It doesn’t follow that somebody who could do all of this wouldn’t have thoughts until/unless they were treated as having them; that would be reference dependence.
So just as an unconnected example, illustrating that distinction: suppose I defined ‘beautiful’ as “would cause pleasure in someone”. Now, then I’ve instituted a sense dependence between beauty and that sense and pleasure; if you can’t understand the concept of pleasure, you can’t understand the concept of beauty, which is a response dependent dependently defined consequence of it.
But now we ask, would there still be beauty if there were no pleasure? Were there beautiful sunset sunsets before there were any people to feel pleasure? That would be the reference dependence question. We say sure because they would have caused pleasure (if there were anyone there to feel it). And we can say, in a possible world in which there never were humans, it still could be that if there were, they would have responded to the sunsets with pleasure.
So, we could say there’s a sense dependence between these concepts, but there doesn’t need to be a reference dependence between doesn’t mean you can’t have the one without having the other it just means you can’t understand what one of them is without understanding the other.
So the claim would be that’s the relation between the thoughts and our normative attitudes are social attitudes. It’s not that the thoughts pop into existence at that point for them.
People with romantic views of language: Derrida and Nietzsche. These are compatible with Wittgenstein believing language has no downtown.
Sellars disagrees: the language-language inferential transitions are of the first importance among those because what makes the entries and exits language entries and exits is the way they connect to the inferential moves. And so he would say to Derrida, “yes, we do all of these other wonderful things with the language, but that’s all parasitic on the meanings that things are given because of the role they play in the space of reasons... now, once you’ve got that up and running, once you’ve got those meanings to work with, now you can start to do other playful things with it, e.g. use them metaphorically. All sorts of things become possible. But that’s in principle a superstructure on this structure."
Sellars story of how ‘the light dawns slowly over the whole’.
Both the infant and Koko the gorilla can be trained into a language (in the form of conforming to ought-to-be’s). At some point the human makes a jump - they have the concept and can be a trainer of others. What’s the nature of that jump?
For Sellars, this is a change in normative status, not a lightbulb that went off in one’s head. Like the change on your 21st birthday, when suddenly doing the very same thing, making the same pen scratches that you could have made the day before, would not be obliging yourself to pay the bank a certain amount of money every every month for the next 30 years. But after your 21st birthday, when you scratch your pen in exactly the same (physically descriptively, matter-of-factually) way, all of a sudden it has a hugely different normative significance because now you will be held responsible. You’ll be taken to have undertaken commitment in a way in which you were not eligible to undertake that commitment by doing the very same thing descriptively, the day before.
When you get good enough at the language game moves, you do get acknowledged by the community. We don’t characterize this physically-descriptively because we’re not describing someone / some matter-of-factual boundary that has been crossed. We’re not describing the child, we’re placing the child in the space of reasons.
It’s the difference between the one and a half year old, who toddles in to the living room. And as her first full sentence says, “Daddy, the house is on fire." Well, one doesn’t think that she has claimed that the house is on fire. She’s managed to put these words together, this is good. If the four year old comes into the living room and says “Daddy, the house was on fire", you hold her responsible, you say “how do you know? Did you smell smoke? And you know, what should we be doing? What follows if the house is on fire? What should we be doing?" You take her to have claimed this to have undertaken a commitment and you hold her responsible for it. The difference is not some light that’s going on. It’s a difference in normative status, ultimately a difference in social status.
This is the difference between just conforming to the pattern, and actually making claims. The radically anti-Cartesian aspect of Sellars is that this is also the the difference between conforming to the pattern and having thoughts at all.
However, as Dennett points out: you can treat any even inanimate object as an intentional system, e.g. this table as having the one desire that remain at the center of the universe. And the one belief that it is currently at the center of the universe, which is why it resists us moving it. (by extension, we treat our cats and dogs this way). So we should only treat things as thinking if we have to. Brandom takes an opposite view, that you should always treat something as talking if you can (note this is a very high bar).
The period prior to the child’s mastery and social status as a language speaker has some peculiarities. His verbal behavior would express his thoughts but, to put it paradoxically, the child could not express them. The child isn’t in a position to intentionally say that things are thus-and-so, even though it is in a position to say that things are thus-and-so. So there’s a question: which comes first, speaker’s meaning or semantic meaning?
Semantic meaning is a matter of what the words mean. No agent involved in that. In English, the word ‘molybdenum’ means the noble metal with 42 protons. Contrast with “When Humpty Dumpty says ‘glory’, he means a nice knockdown, drag-out fight”. Grice says speaker meaning comes first. Sellars says that is a Cartesian way of thinking about things, that the primary meaning is what words mean in the language process.
If I claim the notebook is made out of copper, I have (whether I know it or not), committed it to melting at 1084 oC and that it conducts electricity. My words mean those things, whether or not I mean to.
The kid produces vocal (not yet verbal) noises until he is a member of the language community (his verbal noises conform to enough ought-to-be’s).
As soon as he can say something, that’s the expression of a thought. To take him to be saying is to be taking him to be thinking out loud. It’s a further stage, when he can take expressing that thought as the object of an intention, and intentionally do as an action that say, before that, that’s just an act, it’s a performance, he can reliably produce appropriately, but not yet intentionally produce. An adult could be in this situation: Auction example. That’s the sort of position that the kid (who’s just crossed the line into being able to say something) is: she can produce a vocalization that will hold her responsible for, and which, accordingly, we take to express a thought. But she doesn’t yet have the concept. So, she can have the concept of its being red or the house being on fire. But not yet, the concept of endorsing something, or of making a claim that he’s saying can be a later development. And you need that concept in order to intend to be making a claim.
Important to make distinctions between different types of saying:
mere utterance (position of 1 year old)
saying that things are thus-and-so
having mastered the entries/exits/language-language moves, but no metalinguistic concepts
Could be called “merely thinking out loud”
Can perform speech acts.
Can express that something is read or even a desire for something (“I’m taking that’)
intentionally saying (telling someone) that things are thus-and-so
need concepts of asserting/believing as well as concepts of thus-and-so
Can perform speech actions.
Self consciousness.
We need to think of the child as being able to give evidence without the concept of evidence. This is important in the story of how the language game gets off the ground with the early hominids. But we have real experience with this: when teaching logic, it’s helpful to teach students to have the practical mastery of writing proofs (prior to them having the concept of a proof). They first get familiar with the symbol pushing game. (proof is a strong form of evidence). This is very common in mathematics education.
This lecture was delivered on September 23, 2009.
It concerns [13] and has two parts:
Part 1: Counterfactuals and dispositions.
Part 2: Causal modalities. (the focus of this lecture).
Uses Principia Mathematica notation which takes some time to learn.
Goodman has let the formalism of classical extensional logic mislead him in thinking about counterfactuals. He thought we could build up to counterfactuals from extensional logical vocabulary. The kind that can be built up by extensional logical vocabulary Sellars calls subjunctive identicals.
Goodman is impressed in Fact fiction and Forecast, with the difference between the claim ‘All copper melts at 1084 oC’ and ‘all the coins in my pocket are copper’. The first supports counterfactual reasoning (“if this coin in my pocket were copper, it’d melt at 1084 oC") whereas if this nickel coin were in my pocket, it wouldn’t be made of copper. However we can do some limited form of counterfactual reasoning: “if I pulled a coin out of my pocket, it would be copper”. We can always rephrase such counterfactuals (accidental generalizations) as a statement about something identical to an actual object. (The distinction is less sharp between genuine counterfactuals and subjunctive identicals is less sharp than he thinks, according to Brandom)
Makes distinction.
Defines a disposition.
Subjunctive conditional: if \(X\) were \(\psi\)’d, it would \(\phi\).
(example?)
Counterfactual conditional: if \(X\) had been \(\psi\)’d, it would have \(\phi\)’d.
These are both counterfactuals but very different:
If Oswalt didn’t shoot Kennedy, then some one else did.
If Oswalt didn’t shoot Kennedy, then someone else would have.
A kind term
More than a mere predicate: in addition to criteria of application, also have criteria of identity and individuation.
Two flavors: proper individuating terms as well as mass terms (which requires something like ’cup of’ to individuate)
Condition term
Intervention term
Result term
Canonical example: “If you put the sugar in water, it will dissolve.”
Distinct from a capacity claim: “Sugar has the capacity to dissolve" is a claim that there exists a condition and intervention such that the result obtain.
Sellars first big idea: what was needed was a functional theory of concepts (especially alethic/normative modalities), which would make their role in reasoning, rather than their supposed origin and experience their primary feature. Sellars takes modal expressions to be inference licenses.
Jerry Fodor’s theory of semantic content in terms of nomological locking: can’t directly say anything about modality directly. Not alone: Dretske and other teleosemantic literature. Sellars wants to argue this program will never work.
An axial idea of Kant: the framework that makes description possible has features which we can express with words (words whose job is not to describe6 anything, but rather to make explicit features of the framework within which we can describe things).
The framework is often characterized with laws. With alethic modal vocabulary on the object side, normative vocabulary on the subject side.
Kant is concerned with features that are necessary conditions of the possibility of applying descriptive contents. How are statements like that sensibly thought of as true or false? (where the home language game is ordinary descriptive language) Kant says yes, in a sense, but have to be careful. If these kinds of claims are knowledge, what kind of justification is involved in it? Can we think of them as expressing even a kind of empirical knowledge? (after all, we learned laws of nature empirically, it seems). We have to think about the relationship between the framework and what you can say, in the framework, and what you can say about the framework. Kant was the first one worried about all that stuff. Sellars wants to find a meta framework for talking about the relations between talk within that framework of description, and talk about that framework of description.
Semantic nominalism was universally held until Kant. (philosophy today hasn’t yet graduated from its Humean to its Kantian phase)
If you could argue that standing in counterfactually, robust inferential relations to other descriptive terms, was an essential feature of the descriptive content of a concept (and you could argue that modal vocabularies had the expressive job of making those explicit), then you’d be in a position to argue for the Kant-Sellars thesis about modality. That would be to say that the expressive job of modal vocabulary is to make explicit the inferential relations between descriptive concepts (these are invisible to the empiricist).
Fork in road: Hume+Quine, or Kant+Sellars.
Labels are not descriptions. There’s more to describing than labeling.
Consider mere labels. Elements on a tray have red or blue dots. Have they been described? If so, what have they been described as? If we add things to the tray, we don’t know whether they deserve red or blue labels. At the very least, descriptions need a practice for applying to new cases. We can throw that in but still not have a description.
Suppose I’m trying to give you the concept of gleeb. I give you an infalliable gleebness tester. Do you have a description?
Sellars: “It’s only because the expressions in terms of which we describe objects, locate those objects in a space of implications that they describe it all rather than merely label.”
This is what a mere classifier have.
What’s the difference between me and a parrot who has been trained to say ‘red’ when presented a red object. The parrot isn’t describing, but I am because my noise is situated in a space of implications: something follows for me from classifying that thing is red (that it’s colored that it’s spatially extended, that if it’s a Macintosh Apple, it’s right). And furthermore, other things can be evidence for the claim that it Scarlet is evidence for it or that it’s a right Macintosh, Apple is evidence for it. And it excludes other classifications. That monochromatic patch is not green, if it’s red, and so on.
The classifier focuses only on the circumstances of application, not the consequences of application. A way to answer what the red and blue dots describe an element as is to say what follows from something having a blue or red dot (e.g. things labelled red are to be discarded). Now we have some descriptive content associated with the label.
Verificationism / classical american pragmatism focused purely on the consequences of application.
To say we need both circumstances and consequences is to say that the inferences the concept plays into is an essential part of a concept.
If the only inferences we could make were truth functional relations, then a gleeb detector like thing could be sufficient to capture the concept of gleeb fully; however, we care about counterfactually robust inferences.
You can’t count as understanding (i.e. grasp the meaning of) any descriptive expression / concept, unless you distinguish at least some of the inferences that it’s involved (i.e. some of the connections within that space of implications) as counterfactually robust (i.e. ones that would still obtain, even if something that is true wasn’t, or something that isn’t true was). The claim is not that there are particular counterfactual inferences you need, but that you need at least some to have the concept.
Examples:
Chestnut trees produce chestnuts
Unless they’re immature / blighted
Whether or not it’s raining on them now wouldn’t affect the fact that chestnut trees produce chestnuts
Dry, well-made matches light if you strike them
Not if there’s not enough oxygen
The position of a distant beetle on a tree that doesn’t affect whether this match lights
The hungry lioness would chase the nearby Gazelle
Not if it were struck by lightning
But it would, whether or not the hyena were watching it
Q: do we have to have overlap in our distinctions we made to communicate about the same concept? A: The conceptual content itself is a norm that settles which inferences are correct and which are incorrect. Then, you and I may have different views about where that line is drawn. And what makes it possible for us to communicate (to agree or to disagree) is that we’ve bound ourselves by the same norm by using the same word. You may think the melting point of copper is different from what I think it is. But we can still be disagreeing about copper because there’s a fact of the matter about what you’re committed to, on that issue, when you use the word ‘copper’.
Q: Is this a counter-example? You are asked to bring a thing to your lab (it just landed from an alien planet - you can’t make any inferences about it). A: It’s complicated. Firstly, ‘thing’ or ‘object’ is not a sortal - you can’t count them (they’re pro-sortals, placeholders for sortals). If we supply one (e.g. place-occupying piece of mass - which would suffice give us some counterfactually robust inferences). If you don’t supply one, you haven’t thought about it. Related to Wittgenstein’s plate example.
Kant says concepts are rules for judgment we bind ourselves by. That doesn’t settle the question of how much of the law we need to know in order to bind ourselves by it. I don’t have to know much about molybdenum to refer to molybdenum.
Semantic paradigm is the “name-bearer” relationship. E.g. the ‘Fido’-Fido relation, between the name ‘Fido’ and the dog, Fido. Predicates/properties are just names that stick to the set.
If we stick together labels, we get descriptions (not a primitive name bearer relation, but one we can understand in terms of name-bearer relations). That’s what language lets us do. Describe/classify things (as falling under languages).
Sellars calls this descriptivism: what you do with language is describe things.
You find this not only in anglophone tradition but also in a pure form in Hussurl / semiotics. Derrida rejects Hussurl because there are some phenomena that can’t be related by sign-signified relations, but he addresses it by saying it’s all signs.
Kant found sentences special: you don’t describe things with them, you say things with them. Theory of judgment. The Tractatus has no room for statements of natural law. For normative statements, it retreats into mysticism.
Semantic nominalism is atomistic - the relation of a name and its bearer doesn’t turn on anything else.
From three premises:
what you need to move from labeling to describing is situation in a space of implications
space of implications must draw lines between implications that will between counterfactual circumstances under which the implication would still be good, and those in which wouldn’t
the expressive job, not in the first instance, a descriptive job that’s characteristic of modal vocabulary is to make explicit those range those implications and those ranges of counterfactual robustness
Put another way, suppose Sellars is right that modal expressions function as inference licenses. If it could be argued that those counterfactually robust inferences are essential to articulating the content of ordinary empirical descriptive concepts, then you’d have an argument to the effect that the capacity to use modal concepts what modal concepts make explicit is implicit already in the use even of ordinary empirical, descriptive, non modal concepts.
It’s explicit in Sellars, all but explicit in Kant. Some consequences:
modal vocabulary is not something that you can casually add to ordinary descriptive vocabulary, like culinary vocabulary. Rather, the distinctive expressive job of modal vocabulary is to articulate the inferential connections among descriptive concepts in virtue of which they have the content that they do.
just in being able to use ordinary empirical descriptive vocabulary, non modal vocabulary anyone already knows how to do everything they need to know how to do in order to use modal vocabulary. They merely make explicit what is implicit in non-modal concepts.
One cannot be in the predicamant that Hume took himself to be in. We can teach you how to use modal vocabulary. You may not have a word for it yet. That’s what we’ll give you. But you already know how to do everything you need to know how to do to use that word to talk with ‘necessity’, ‘possibility’ and the subjunctive.
Description and explanation are two sides of one coin.
Revolution in Anglophone philosophy, taking three phases:
Kripke’s possible-worlds semantics for modal logic (algebraic properties accessibility relation determine which modal system we’re in)
Quine was a skeptic of modal talk, said that we didn’t know what we really meant when talking about it.
His concerns became unpopular with this development, as Kripke’s semantics gave people the impression that we had a grasp on what we meant (in fact, alethic modal talk became the philosophical ground level for explaining other puzzling things (such as intentionality)).
Quine thinks his objection is not yet satisfied; of course we can explain modal concepts in terms of other modal concepts - what do we mean by possible world? What do we mean by accessibility?
The previous development is only for modal logic, but Montague, David Kaplan, David Lewis, Stalnaker, etc. extended it to work for non-logical semantics as well. For example:
In Lewis’ General Semantics [14], if we decide to treat objects as semantic interpretant of our names, sets of possible worlds as the semantic interpretant of our sentences, then one-place predicates correspond to functions from objects to sets of possible worlds.
‘walks’ is a function from objects to the worlds in which that object is walking.
adverbs, like ‘slowly’, is a function from one-place predicates to one-place predicates.
This apparatus gives us a way to talk precisely about certain distinctions that come up in philosophy language. E.g. adverbs come in two flavors:
Attributive: ‘walked slowly’ which implies one walked at all
Non-attributive: ‘walked in one’s imagination’
Kripke’s Naming and Necessity [15]
Introduced us to contingent a priori and metaphysical necessity
Brandom says: the second is the most important, but Quine’s objection was not addressed by Kripke’s semantics nor the fact that it’s useful in semantics to be able to use Kripke’s apparatus. The reason why we should have gained comfortablity with alethic modal language is actually the Kant-Sellars thesis, which dispels empiricist worries of modal concepts being unintelligible.
But hardly anyone knows about that argument. If they did, it would color our current focuses and interests. For the Kant-Sellars thesis pertains to causal/physical modalities. But nowadays, the center of philosophical thought worries about logical modalities and metaphysical modalities - causal modality is boring to them. “We’re distracted by the shiny, new playground that Kripke offered us and lost sight of the modality that’s philosophically most significant."
Name | Mr C | Mr E |
---|---|---|
Stands for | constant conjunction | entailment |
Represents | empiricists | rationalists |
Core of truth | statements of necessary connection do not describe matter of factual states of affairs | what you’re doing when you make a modal claim is endorsing the propriety of a pattern of material inference |
Core mistake | the only thing you can do with language is describe matter of factual states of affairs (therefore, laws must be descriptions of regularities) | statements of necessity describe entailment (still a descriptivist POV) |
Sellars take the dialectic through many turns instead of just saying what he thinks. He pretends to be even-handed until deciding to focus on tweaking Mr E.’s theory to make it work.
Need to distinguish four related types of claims:
The practical endorsement of infering that things are \(B\)’s from their being \(A\)’s.
This is presupposed by the act of describing (Kant-Sellars thesis)
The explicit statement that one may infer the applicability of \(B\) from the applicability of \(A\)
This can be asserted without understanding the expressions \(A\) and \(B\)
I.e., it’s syntactic; just a statement about the use of language
Someone who doesn’t speak German can still say “If \(x\) is ‘rot’, then \(x\) is ‘farbig’."
The statement that \(A\) physically entails \(B\)
The statement that \(A\)’s are necessarily \(B\)’s.
Mr E was getting the content of modal statements wrong; they aren’t about language.
That some inference is ok is something that is conveyed by a modal claim, but it is not what is said. (Analogy: John says/asserts/means “The weather is good today”, but John conveys “John thinks the weather is good today” and John does not say “John thinks the weather is good today.”). Related to this quote.
What Sellars’ conclusion ought to be: what one is doing in making a modal assertion is endorsing a pattern of material inference. No need to take a stand on semantics. This is an expressivist view of modal vocabulary. Analogous to expressivism in ethics: what you are doing in saying someone ought to do \(X\) is endorsing doing \(X\). We can try to understand the semantic/descriptive content7 in terms of what one is doing when we use the expressions.
Sellars wants to say it is the correctness of inferences connecting descriptive terms that make modal claims. Simultaneously, modal claims do not say anything about inferences.
It’s important that notion of saying is wider than describing. This is the denial of semantic descriptivism.
The pragmatic force associated with the modal claim is endorsing a pattern of inference.
What one says is that being a \(B\) follows from being an \(A\). This is not a statement about inferences, it is a statement about a consequential relation. When one says “\(x\) being copper is incompatible with \(x\) being an insulator", one is making a claim about the world (even if it is not describing it in the narrow sense). These are facts about what follows from what in the world. Given the auxillary hypothesis that our word ‘copper’ means copper, there are things we can say about inferences, but the fact that we need that auxillary hypothesis is proof that the statement itself isn’t about inferences.
So modal claims are descriptive in the wide sense but not the narrow sense.
There are some serious concerns, though. Consider "There exist causal connections which have not yet been discovered". This is analogous to accepting the early emotivist line in ethics (thinking ‘ought’ is a perfectly good concept, though not a descriptive one ... such that ‘Everybody ought to keep promises’ contextually implies a wish, on the speaker’s part, that promise keeping were a universal practice), and was then confronted with such statements as “There are obligations which have not yet been recognized” and “Some of the things we think of as obligations are not obligations”
Quote: “It is therefore important to realize that the presence in the object language of the causal modalities (and of the logical modalities and of the deontic modalities) serves not only to express existing commitments, but also to provide the framework for the thinking by which 303 we reason our way (in a manner appropriate to the specific subject matter) into the making of new commitments and the abandoning of old. And since this framework essentially involves quantification over predicate variables, puzzles over the ‘existence of abstract entities’ are almost as responsible for the prevalence in the empiricist tradition of ‘nothing-but-ism’ in its various forms (emotivism, philosophical behaviorism, phenomenalism) as its tendency to assimilate all discourse to describing.”
If we are to take causal modalities, seriously / at face value, we’re going to have to worry about what abstract objects and what properties are.
Brandom thinks Sellars could have a simpler/more satisfying conclusion to the essay, but Sellars’ nominalism (denial of existence for abstract objects/properties) prevents him from doing so.
In Brandom’s view, material inferences are not monotonic. The job of some scientific languages is to find concepts where we can state monotonic consequence relations. We can do that in fundamental physics, but hardly ever in the special sciences.
Hegel says, “By conceptual, I mean, what’s articulated by relations of determinant negation8 and mediation9".10 He says, the objective world, as it is, independently of our activities, is conceptually articulated. It has a conceptual structure because he’s a modal realist about it.
He thinks there are laws of nature. He thinks some things really follow from other things. For instance, that if a body with finite mass is accelerated, then a force was applied to it. he thinks that’s a consequence, and the remaining relatively at rest, and having a force supplied you those are incompatible. Those are incompatible properties.
So he says, the objective world has a conceptual structure already that has nothing to do with our conceiving activity. We can see that as something else. Yes, our commitments can also stand in relations of material consequence and in compatibility, but the world, just as it comes, is already in conceptual shape.
Let ‘possible world’ mean a physically possible world11. This conceptual apparatus can be thought of simply as a way of expressing what it is for two properties to be incompatible or to stand in a material consequential relation.
So we can express (in the language of possible worlds) the fact that it follows from (as a consequence) something’s being copper that it melts at 1084 oC, for example.
David Lewis is presented as an example of misusing possible world semantics. He discards the connection between inference and the possible worlds. He takes the descriptivist position that all one can do is describe with language, but then says he is not an actualist (you can describe non-actual worlds in the same sense that you can describe the coin in your pocket as copper).
What is lost by merging description in the narrow sense and description in the wide sense? The connection to semantics. We’ve also gained an additional problem of justifying our claims to knowledge of the non-actual worlds.
This lecture was delivered on September 30, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on October 7, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on October 14, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on October 21, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on October 28, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on November 11, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on November 18, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on December 2, 2009.
This lecture was delivered on August 28, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on October 30, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on November 5, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on November 13, 2019.
This lecture was delivered in late November, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on December 4, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on September 04, 2019.
Three historical currents:
England: Bertrand Russell and GE Moore. Introducing analytic philosophy against absolute idealism (championed by Bradley, who was influenced by Hegel-inspired T.H. Greene who was reacting negatively to dominant British empiricists). Sellars admired On Denoting.
American: At turn of the century, German idealism dominated (Josiah Royce more popular speaker than Williams James). Two movements recoiling against this: American pragmatism and "new realism/critical realism" (AKA trinonminalists, including Sellars’ father, which lost to pragmatism and logical empiricism).
German/Austrian: Marbourg (natural science focus of Kant) -> Carnap + Vienna Circle. Three periods, Aufbau (radical reductive empiricism: all statements must be definable in terms of immediate experience + logical vocabulary). Carnap then lightens up (in response to CI Lewis) and says statements must at least be able to be supported by evidence that comes from experience (replacing biconditional EXPERIENCE<->THEORETICAL with just a conditional EXPERIENCE->THEORETICAL;’ there’s a surplus on the theoretical side). In parallel, Frankfurt school (Adorono/Walter Benjamin/Habermas), concerned with culture (and with Marxist inflection).
Tools of the syntactical phase of logical empiricism not adequate to address all general philosophical problems - it was improved by the semantic dimensions. He wants to turn the crank again to add a pragmatic dimension.
What did Sellars see of value in the reductivist Carnap? Carnap quote: “A symbol is introduced (or, if it is already in use, is subsequently legitimized) by determining under what conditions it is to be employed in the representation of a state of affairs. The introduction or legitimization of the word ’horse’, for instance, comes about by determining the conditions which must hold if we’re to call something a horse, hence through statement of the distinguishing features of a horse or the definition of horse. We say of the symbol (that has been introduced / legitimized in such a way that we think is at least capable of legitimization) that it designates a concept. So, the symbol of a concept is a rule-governed symbol. Whether it be defined or not. Its use should above all be rule-governed. The symbol should not be employed in any old arbitrary way, but rather, in a determinate consistent way. Uniformity in the mode of employemnet can be secured either by explicitly laying down rules or merely through constant habit, linguistic usage. We have not yet said anything about what a concept is, but only for what it is for a symbol to designated a concept and this is all that can be said with any precision. But it’s also enough, for when talk of concepts is meaningful, it invariably addresses concepts designated by symbols or concepts that can in principle be so designated. And such talk is basically alaways about these symbols and the laws of their use. The formation of a concept consists in the establishment of the law concerning the use of the symbol it is a word in the representation in a state of affairs”. Link to sellars quote: “Grasp of a concept is always mastery of the use of a word" Even in the Aufbau, Carnap thinks of rule-governedness of symbols being crucial to the meaning of concepts.
One way to understand the core program of analytical philosophy: the project of elaborating the meanings of a puzzling vocabulary in terms of a base vocabulary (unproblematic) with logical vocabulary. Naturalism (trying to describe intensions/norms in terms of natural science)/empiricism (trying to describe laws in terms of sense experience) as an example. (Kris: is ordinary language philosophy an example?) If it’s not possible to elaborate, then the vocabulary is seens as defective in some way.
Brandom tries to synthesize this view with pragmatism as exemplified by Wittgenstein/Sellars.
This lecture was delivered on September 11, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on September 16, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on September 25, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on October 2, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on October 9, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on October 16, 2019.
This lecture was delivered on October 23, 2019.
“It’s not about our grip on concepts12; it’s about the concept’s grip on us."
“One cannot open the door enough for Kant to get through while being able to slam it shut before Hegel gets through. (Hegel was too interesting of a reader of Kant)"
It’s not what’s between your ears, it’s what’s between you and your peers.
Rudolf Carnap was a German philosopher, 1891-1970.
Carnap was a kind of pragmatist: - he believed that we should be completely pragmatic about our choice of language - However, once the language is fixed, the world dictates what are true or false theories in that language.
This relies on a language-theory distinction that Quine argued against.
Stanley Cavell was an American philosopher, 1926-2018.
(in progress notes) - Main question: does what we ordinarily say/mean have a direct+deep control over what we can philosophically say/mean? - Goal: respond to objections to the methodology of ‘ordinary language philosophy’ (by Mates) - Distinguish 3 kinds of statements about ordinary language - 1. Statements which produce instances of what is said in a language - “We do say … but we don’t say …” - “We ask whether … but we don’t ask whether …” - 2. Like above, but with explications - “When we say …, we imply/suggest/say …” - “We don’t say … unless we mean …” - 3. Generalizations, tested by reference to the first two types - Working example: disagreement between Austin and Ryle - 1. Austin: “We say ‘The gift was made voluntarily’’’ (type 1) - 2. Ryle: “It makes sense… to ask whether a boy was responsible for breaking a window, but not whether he was responsible for finishing his homework in good time” (type 1) - 3. Ryle: “‘voluntary’/‘involuntary’ are applied as adjectives to actions which ought not be done” (type 3) - Praise of Ryle’s generalization: - Philosophical use of “voluntary” is distinct/disconnected from “volition” - People think confusedly as if everything is either appropriately described as voluntary or involuntary - Criticism of Ryle’s generalization: - Saying there must be something morally fishy about the action that is described as voluntary is not general enough. - However, the fact Ryle’s attempt to generalize has errors does not invalidate his methodology (that he can make type 1 and type 2 statements about ordinary language). - Philosophical problem that arises from type 2 statements - “We say A where B is the case … we misuse A when B is not the case” - is there a logical relation between A and B? - Logical statements hold between statements, not between a statement and the world. - Kris: perhaps the logical relation is between “speaker says A” IMPLIES (“World is B” IFF “Speaker is competent at the language”) - So call the meaning of A its semantics and the pratical conditions of its utterance its pragmatics - “Voluntary” does not mean “fishy” - Mates’ formula for computing pragmatic value of an expression: “He wouldn’t say that unless he …” - But surely there must be something logical, since something about B must follow from the utterance of A! - The speaker “MUST MEAN” something is fishy if they call it voluntarily (the must is more critical here than the ‘mean’) - Mates’ formula does not seem to give insight into the necessity here. -
A French philosopher, 1930-2005.
Philosophers have had this idea that reason is central to talk and thought. But we hardly ever actually reason with each other or argue or infer; look at all the playful things we can do with language.
So Derrida will write an essay where his interpretation of Hegel crucially turns on the fact that his name in French rhymes with ‘eagle’ [17]. For another essay, what’s really important in interpreting it is how wide the margins were in the first edition of it.
One of the things he’s trying to do is de-center us from thinking - “what does this signify” - “what is the rational meaning of this?” - “what is the inferential role of this?” - “What does it stand for?”
John Dewey was an American pragmatist philosopher, 1959-1952.
Dewey wants the distinctions between science and philosophy to be rubbed out and replaced with an uncontroversial notion of intelligence trying to solve problems and provide meanings.
While this is a distinction that Rorty, too, wishes to undermine, Rorty criticizes Dewey (in Experience in Nature [18]) as wanting to “use the term ‘experience’ as an incantatory device to blur every conceivable distinction.”
A Scottish philosopher, 1711-1776.
Even our best understanding of actual observable empirical facts doesn’t yield an understanding of rules relating or otherwise governing them.
We can get the facts, but not these non-logical, non-relations of ideas (inferential relations among them).
This as an epistemological point: how do we know such statements can be justified? But it’s also a semantic point: given what you can mean, on Hume’s account of impressions and ideas, there’s nothing you could mean other than constant conjunction, when talking about a non-logical relation among these things.
The facts don’t settle which of the things that actually happened had to happen, nor which of the things that didn’t happen were still possible, i.e. not ruled out by laws concerning what did happen.
So, Hume, and following him, Quine took it that epistemologically (but mostly semantically) fastidious philosophers faced a stark choice, either: - show how to explain what’s expressed by modal vocabulary in non modal terms - learn to live without it: Show how you can do what you need to do without talk about laws and possibility and necessity and so on.
Hume saw that there was nothing that you could be labeling (or in his sense, describing) by these statements of laws. This is why Hume woke \(\ref{kant|Kant}\) from his dogmatic slumbers.
This stems from a kind of semantic nominalism that drew sharp lines around what you couldn’t describe. Hume understood saying/thinking something as describing something. It falls out of this that saying how things might have been (or how things had to be) isn’t describing anything. These are the consequences of a theory of description (in the narrow sense) and a descriptivist theory of language. Kant looks at Newton’s physics and determines that these conclusions are wrong, so there must be some non-descriptive thing we can do.
A German metaphysical rationalist, 1646-1716.
A German philosopher, 1844-1900.
From [20]:
Truth is a mobile army of metaphors, metonyms, anthropomorphisms, in short, a sum of human relations which were poetically and rhetorically heightened, transferred, and adorned, and after long use seem solid, canonical, and binding to a nation. Truths are illusions about which it has been forgotten that they are illusions.
Huw Price is an Australian philosopher, born 1953.
An American philosopher, 1931-2007.
From [21]:
To treat beliefs not as representations but as habits of action, and words not as representations but as tools, is to make it pointless to ask, ‘Am I discovering or inventing, making or finding?’ There is no point in dividing up the organisms’ interaction with the environment in this way. Consider an example. We normally say that a bank account is a social construction rather than an object in the natural world, whereas a giraffe is an object in the natural world rather than a social construction. Bank accounts are made, giraffes are found. Now the truth in this view is simply that if there had been no human beings there would still have been giraffes, whereas there would have been no bank accounts. But this causal independence of giraffes from humans does not mean that giraffes are what they are apart from human needs and interests.
On the contrary, we describe giraffes in the way we do, as giraffes, because of our needs and interests. We speak a language which includes the word ‘giraffe’ because it suits our purposes to do so. The same goes for words like ‘organ’, ‘cell’, ‘atom’, and so on - the names of the parts out of which giraffes are made, so to speak. All the descriptions we give of things are descriptions suited to our purposes. No sense can be made, we pragmatists argue, of the claim that some of these descriptions pick out ‘natural kinds’ - that they cut nature at the joints. The line between a giraffe and the surrounding air is clear enough if you are a human being interested in hunting for meat. If you are a language-using ant or amoeba, or a space voyager observing us from far above, that line is not so clear, and it is not clear that you would need or have a word for ‘giraffe’ in your language. More generally, it is not clear that any of the millions of ways of describing the piece of space time occupied by what we call a giraffe is any closer to the way things are in themselves than any of the others. Just as it seems pointless to ask whether a giraffe is really a collection of atoms, or really a collection of actual and possible sensations in human sense organs, or really something else, so the question, ‘Are we describing it as it really is?’ seems one we never need to ask. All we need to know is whether some competing description might be more useful for some of our purposes.
“To claim that the relationship between the framework of sense contents and that of physical objects can be construed on the phenomalist model (NB: to think of physical objects as constellations of sense contents) is to commit oneself to the idea that there are inductively confirmable generalizations (NB: subjunctive conditionals) about sense contents which are in principle capable of being formulated without the language of physical things. This idea is a mistake.” (phenomenalism)
“To say that a person desired to do A, thought it his duty to do B, but was forced to do C, is not to describe him as one might describe a scientific specimin. One does indeed describe him, but one does something more. And it’s this ‘something more’ which is the irreducible core of the framework of persons. In what does this ‘something more’ consist? To think of a featherless bird as a person is to think of it as a being with which one is bound up in a network of duties. From this point of view, the irreducibility of the personal is the irreducibility of the ought or the is. But even more basic than this to think of a featherless biped as a person is to construe its behavior in terms of actual or potential membership in an embracing group, each member of which thinks of itself as a member of the group. Let’s call such a group a community."
Deep connection between the normative, the social, and the self-conscious.
“Although describing and explaining are distinguishable, they are also in an important sense inseparable. The descripitive and explanatory resources of language advance hand-in-hand."
These two kinds of discursive activity, one can be describing in a particular act and not explaining (and vice-versa).
Globally, they’re only intelligible in terms of their relation to each other.
The claim that matters: you couldn’t have an (autonomous discursive) language in use that had one and not the other.
The reason is at least that in order to describe something you have to place it in a space of implications (i.e. the above quote)
“The idea that the world can in principle be so described that the description contains no modal expressions is of a piece with the idea that world can in principle be so described such that the description contains no prescriptive expressions.” CDCM.
He doesn’t explicitly say whether it’s a bad idea or not.
He wants to say modal expressions and normative expression belong in a box.
“Exemplification is a quasi-semantical relation, and it (and universals 14) is in the world only in that broad sense in which the world includes linguistic norms and roles viewed from the standpoint of a fellow paritipant."
This plays off Carnap’s notion of ‘quasi-syntactical’.
There’s the narrow view of ‘the world’, that’s the world that science is the measure of all things. And the broader view of the world.
“The means of semantical statements is no more a psychological word than is the ought of ethical statements or the must of modal statements."
I think of this in the following way: the \(\square\) operator can be applied to statements to make them ‘modal’ (which could be alethic, deontic, or many other things like “Jones thinks that ..."). One such \(\square\) is “Semantically, ...” (or, “Literally, ...”). Ordinary statements made in practical life could be interpreted as having an implicit “Pragmatically, ...” (in fact, could we define pragmatics to be that which play this role?)
“Kant was on the right track when he insisted that, just as concepts are essentially (not accidentally) items which can occur in judgments, so judgments (and therefore indirectly concepts) are items that occur essentially (not accidentally) that occur in reasonings or arguments."
Turns a tradition (order of explanation: concepts -> judgments -> inferences) on its head.
“It’s only because the expressions in terms of which we describe objects locate them in a space of implications that they describe at all, rather than merely label."
Describing is what science is the measure of all things about.
You can’t do everything with just classification. It’s not a rich enough concept to get you to descriptions.
“To say that man is a rational animal is to say that man is a creature not of habits but of rules. When God created Atom, He whispered in his ear, ‘In all contexts of action you will recognize rules, if only the rule to grope for rules to recognize. When you cease to recognize rules, you will walk on four feet."
“To make firsthand use of modal expressions / subjunctive conditionals, is to be about the business of explaining a state of affairs or justifying an assertion." [13]
Note we explain an (actual) state of affairs. We justify an assertion (non-actual, in the space of reasons).
“The language of modalities is a transposed language of norms.”
(Related to this quote)
What is the connection between the (alethic) modal sense of must and the normative sense of must.
Carnap uses ‘transposed’ to talk about an unquoted word used in a sentence as a transposed mode of speech (about use of a quoted-word). E.g. “Red is a quality.” vs “ ‘Red’ is a one-place predicate.”
“Once the tautology ‘the world is described by descriptive concepts’ is freed from the idea that the business of all non-logical concepts is to describe, the way is clear to an ungrudging recognition that many expressions which empiricists have relegated to second-class citizenship in discourse are not inferior, they’re just different."
Descriptive concepts are not the only kinds of concepts. There is a temptation of empiricists in assimilating all expressions to descriptive expressions (such that anything not intelligible as descriptive is defective).
The negation of this is called decriptivism.
The Tractatus was supremely descriptivist, yet made a key advance by noting that logical expressions play a different kind of role (prior to Tractatus, Russell would be looking into the world to try to see what distinguishes positive from negative facts, when he should not have been looking to the world).
Sellars extends this even further. The later Wittgenstein saw language as playing an unsurveyable variety of roles.
Most interesting philosophical concepts come with a “-ing” “-ed” distinction that’s crucial. Is a justification an act of justifying vs what’s justified (related Agrippean trilemma). Is an experience an act of experiencing vs what’s experienced.
“A rule, properly speaking, isn’t a rule unless it lives in behavior, rule-regulated behavior. Even rule-violating behavior. Linguistically we always operate within a framework of living rules. To talk about rules is to move outside the talked about rules into another framework of living rules. The snake which sheds its skin lives within another. In attempting to grasp rules as rules from without, we are trying to have our cake and eat it. To describe rules is to describe the skeletons of rules. The rule is lived, not described." [22]
You can’t be inside the rules and outside talking about them at the same time.
"In the dimension of describing and explaining the world, science is the measure of all of things. Of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not"
[23]
The opening qualification is important but usually left out.
“In characterizing an episode or a state as knowing, we are not giving an empirical description of it. We are placing it in the logical space of reasons, of justifying and being able to justify what one says." [23]
Note, there’s nothing too special about knowing. He could also have said believing.
We’re doing something, an act that’s not describing something.
Relates to the scientium mensure quote - we have an example of something (describing knowledge) as something that science is not the measure of all things about.
Rorty characterized Sellars readership as "right wing" (ones who felt the greatest philosophical illumination from “scientium mensura") vs "left wing" (who rally behind the “space of reasons").
The Vienna circle, too, had two wings (the naturalist wing (Neurath) and the empiricist wing (Schlict)) in tension (e.g. empiricists making sense of modal statements). Carnap struggled to hold them together.
Joke: Rorty says “I hope the left and right wing Sellarsians can sort their differences out in the end more peacefully than the left and right wing Hegelians did, who settled it once and for all at a 6 month seminar called The Battle of Stalingrad.”
“We’ve established not only that subjunctive conditionals are the expressions of material rules of inference, but that the authority of those rules is not derivative from formal rules. In other words, we’ve shown that material rules of inference are essential to the language we speak, for we make constant use of subjunctive conditions. It’s very tempting to conclude that material rules of inference are essential to languages containing descriptive terms."
“Anything which can properly be called ‘conceptual thinking’ can occur only within a framework of conceptual thinking in terms of which it can be critized, supported, refuted (in short, evaluated). To be able to think is to be able to measure one’s thoughts by standards of correctness, of relevance, of evidence (NB: in the space of justification). In this sense the diversified conceptual framework is a whole which (however sketchy) is prior to its parts, and cannot be construed as a coming to gether of parts which are conceptual in character. The conclusion is difficult to avoid that the transition from preconceptual patterns of behavior to conceptual thinking is a holistic one, a jump to a level of awareness that is irreducibly new. A jump which was the coming of the being of man."
Constrast with Wittegnsteinian image of “light dawning slowly on the whole". Sellars is worried about the mechanism of how this happens.
Born 1912 in Michigan, died in 1989.
An Austrian philosopher, 1889-1951.
“Language has no downtown.” / “Language is a motley” - A view attributed to Wittgenstein by Brandom.
It’s all suburbs. There’s no part of it such that everything else is is arrayed around it as a suburb of it. Sellars disagrees: thinks the downtown is giving and asking for reasons.
From [24]:
The questions: - “What is length?” - “What is meaning?” - “What is the number one?” - etc.
produce in us a mental cramp. We feel that we can’t point to anything in reply to them and yet ought to point to something.
(We are up against one of the great sources of philosophical bewilderment: we try to find a substance for a substantive.)
Combination of Tooth pain parable and descriptivism
Often there are ideas that are closely related, and it becomes ambiguous which idea is ‘first’, if any.
We normally think that the content of judgments are dictated by the content of the concepts used inside of them. This feels especially right for artificial languages:
Take “If it’s a \(P\), then it’s a \(Q\).”
Or, logically: \(\forall x, P(x)\implies Q(x)\)
The meaning of this statement seems to depend on what concepts \(P\) and \(Q\) we substitute in. E.g. with \(P \mapsto {\rm red\ thing},\ Q \mapsto {\rm colored\ thing}\), it’s a good a judgment, whereas \(Q \mapsto {\rm rectangular\ thing}\) would no longer be a good judgment.
However, Kant turned this around (see here). In this view, judgments are prior (in the order of understanding) to concepts.
This is also related to a switch of priority made by Sellars: we normally think of logically-valid inferences (e.g. \(A \land B \implies B \lor C\)) as something we understand prior to particular inferences (e.g. “If it’s red and triangular, then it’s triangular or heavy”). Sellars calls these particular inferences material_inferences and argues that it is only through understanding them that we could understand logically-valid inferences.
One argument for our initial intuition is that the logically-valid inferences are a priori, whereas the particular inferences are a posteriori.15 However, Achilles and the Tortoise feels relevant for arguing against this point of view: the logically-valid inferences exist a priori as abstract mathematical/syntactical objects, but without any practical experience of actually making inferential moves, we don’t have access to them qua inferences.
Tarski’s theory of truth says: if you take meanings for granted, I can give you a truth predicate.
Davidson flipped this on its head, saying: Tarski provided the meanings of a class of terms given how they interact with other propositions.
It feels natural to try to reduce concepts to combinations of sense impressions (this is what Locke/Hume do). This is a mistake that comes from the fact that sense impressions are causally prior to our concepts. This does not mean they are conceptually prior.
Sense data itself is not contentful/conceptual in nature and cannot stand in relations of justification/implication.
Learning philosophy historically, one finds a distinction frequently made between analytic and synthetic statements. We want to put declarative statements into two boxes:
Analytic:
“Cats are mammals”
“Every bachelor is unmarried”
Synthetic:
“There has existed a black dog”
“There are three people in this room right now”
How would we characterize analytic statements? One common way is to say that the truth of analytic statements depends purely on what the constituent terms mean, whereas synthetic statements (additionally) depend on the state of the world.
One of the two dogmas of Two Dogmas of Empiricism by Quine is the notion of analyticity, i.e. that the analytic-synthetic distinction can be made at all.
He argues that the type of information required to make us change our opinion of the truth of “cats are mammals” and any synthetic statement are actually not different in kind.
Quine’s conclusion: we should cease to make the meaning-theory distinction / language-theory distinction / meaning-belief distinction — all there is is the use of our expressions, and the usage is what determines both the meanings and what we take to be true.
Quine’s target is Carnap (who is thinking of artificial languages: first you fix the language and then you go into the world to see which are true in virtue of what they mean).
Anti-bifurcationism coined by Huw Price.
From Pragmatism, Relativism, and Irrationalism “So, a second characterization of pragmatism might go like this: there is no epistemological difference between truth about what ought to be and truth about what is, nor any metaphysical difference between facts and values, nor any methodological difference between morality and science.”
THese are all just statements in vocabularies. Without privileging a nature’s own vocbularty’
In neither case do you need to worry about what makes such-and-such statement in the vocabulary true. What you should worry about is the reason relations within each vocaublary - there will be socioilogical differences between physics and literary theory in how reason relations cone - But the representationalist mistake one can make is thinking that these sociological differences are metaphysical differences in the underlying content.
Two meanings of “\(X\) depends on \(Y\)” that are easily conflated.
To assert a sense dependence of \(X\) on \(Y\) is to say: “.
To assert a reference dependence is to say: “.”
Brandom points out that we can have sense dependence without having reference dependence.
An example is a toy concept of beauty: “\(X\) is beautiful if looking at it elicits pleasure in people.” - This is asserting a sense dependence of beauty on people, but not a reference dependence. - It is intelligible that there could exist beautiful sunsets before there ever were people in the world, or if people never existed.
Matt Teichman hosts a podcast, Elucidations, which features ~30 min interviews with philosophy professors about their work.
July 6, 2009
We want a theory of desire that can answer questions like, given a scenario and a desire, was that desire satisfied?
Notably, we are not asking whether a person with that desire was happy or not afterwards.
Satisfaction is whether or not that state is obtained
Challenging scenario for this view:
A man is rushing to catch a important train to NYC and boards at the last second, only to realize afterward that the train is heading to the wrong destination. Was his desire satisfied?
No - eliminitivist
We reject that the than man desired to get on the train to a wrong destination, because his ‘true’ desire involved to see the doctor in NYC, which is inconsistent with being on the wrong train.
Problem:
The doctor was going to tell him if his disease was curable, so what his ‘true’ desire is the cure, not the train to NYC (this can be done ad infinitum: his true desire is not the cure but rather health -> happiness -> ‘the good’).
I.e. the naive eliminitivist accidentally eliminates all desires other than the desire for ‘the good’.
Yes - separatist
Introduce another desire to make sense of why the man is upset despite the desire being satisfied. The ‘catch-this-train’ desire was satisfied, but ‘get to NYC’ that was not satisfied.
Problem
This account makes the desires seem separate/atomic, but why do they seem so intimiately connected to each other?
If he learned just before that it was going to the wrong destination, his desire to catch the (that) train would instantly vanish.
Makes desires in principle unconnected from what is good for us.
When you want anything, you want more than one thing, so it’s complicated to answer “did you get what you want”.
The man wanted to catch the train AND wanted to get to NYC, those are both aspects of his SINGLE desire.
There is a specific side and a general side to a desire
Object of desire (“catching this train”)
Aim - what makes the object appealing.
Conventional wisdom holds they are both representable merely as states of the world, although they have an complementary relationship
We want to update our belief state to match the world, want to update the world to match our belief state.
This picture is incomplete
Example: feel hungry, desire food.
It can’t be an accident that a bunch of seemingly related desires pop up (want a sandwich downstairs, want pasta from next door, …)
It doesn’t make sense that we desire things in a way that is not possible (want sandwich from Paris, from the moon)
Things make more sense when we break down the structure of a desire:
Object: sandwich from deli downstairs, sandwich
Aim: satisfy the hunger
These thoughts might inspire positive change in fields like economics, where people’s desires are taken to be “given in advance”
Their framework involves setting up a system that optimizes utility, given desires (as the fixed input data).
But rather the desires are adaptive to the world / how things are achieved.
Parents try don’t satisfy children’s desires because they don’t have the right desires. The desires are formed on the reflection of prior experience (knowing what to want, how to achieve it).
The story of the formation of the desire is required towards understanding what it means to satsify it.
Some problems stem from representating a human state of mind as a static object, whereas our beliefs aren’t constant w/r/t time spent in reflection.
Every desire can be chained iteratively until you reach “the good”, but almost never is that entire chain ‘in register’ for real human being. At instant t in time, we are cognizant of a finite number of steps along that chain (we implicitly accept some goals as final, even with more thought power we would view them as instrumental).
Therefore the eliminitivist is not susceptible to Collard’s criticism. Whether the man’s desire was satisfied would be dependent on his mental state while having the desire. If he did not invest enough effort into chaining the desire all the way to The Good, then it’s possible for the desire to be satisfied but the person not (and more likely the fewer links along the chain are ‘in register’).
Collard’s “object”/“aim” structure of a desire seems to be just considering two points along the chain - this is still more nuance than a one-point approximation, but it really is referring to a pair “naive desires” as a desire with bipartite structure.
It is a reasonable strategy to salvage the “separatist” POV by giving an account for the relation between different desired states of the world (they are not atomic anymore)
August 3, 2009
Clarification: “poetry” to Plato is more similar to what we call theatre (performative context).
Plato thought he innovated the distinction between style and content:
Distinguishing the story from the way the poet tells the story
E.g. style could vary between 3rd person, 1st person narration for the same story
The effect of being exposed to poetry: one tries to be many things, instead of one thing.
Background: Plato + Aristotle both believed a good human life is unified
A single goal, so you could say what it was about
(they happened to think the best goal was contemplation of eternal truths).
We share this intuition, though now we also praise people for having a variety of interests.
How can you be a mother and a working professional at once?
We would rather try to make the two identities compatible, rather than try to argue that people should be comfortable/adept at having multiple identities.
What is the distinction between unity and diversity:
A single person does many things (shoemaker has to cut leather, sew, negotiate, …) and these are all ways of expressing a single identity (illusory multiplicity).
Plato objects to the multiple identities.
Also note: Plato not opposed to all poetry, since he thinks it is valuable in early moral development as a form of play.
Rather, we should reform poetry to prevent it from encouraging multiplicity.
Example:
First you are Homer narrating, then you are Achilles, then you are Helen, etc.
We come to enjoy being many people by being exposed to this.
When you seek to be many things, you are no particular thing at all.
The single identity of ‘a poet’ is not a real identity.
Poets were master entertainers, aiming at producing pleasure
Pleasure should be a means to an aim (directs one towards satisfying one’s identity), but pleasure as the goal is not genuine (meaningless pleasure, which is our modern conception of pleasure)
For Plato, then, pleasures can be false, and poets do not provide genuine pleasure.
By aiming at appearances, the thing the poet aims for cannot serve as a genine telos.
A shoemaker does not have to constantly vary his output to stay satisfied, but the poet has to keep changing is stories to keep people interested, because his pleasure is fleeting / they’re not actually satisfying (only seeming to satisfy us).
The difference between going to the gym with the intention of becoming strong vs the intention of going to the gym just to feel like one is a gym person.
We have lots of fleeting/meaningless pleasure that is not actually satisfying (we have to keep varying things to keep interested). Was Plato predicting the emptiness of contemporary society and shallowness of popular culture?
Plato’s remedy is austere: the only goal capable of having the stability of unifying a life is pursuit of reason. (Not incompatible with modern conceptions of the good life, for theists or academic-minded people).
Plato offers valid criticism of entertainment and high culture, but he underestimates the value of certain kinds of play. He didn’t see that we play not at things we want to become, but also things we’re afraid of or want to learn about.
September 1, 2009.
Nietzsche means something different from ethics when using the term morality
He presents himself as a “critic of morality”
Although also talks about “higher moralities” as things he approves of, using the same German word.
Leitner distinguishes these senses by introducing the term “morality in the pejorative sense”
What characterizes the types of morality Nietzsche’s opposed to?
Has particular assumptions about human nature that Nietzsche takes to be false.
E.g. assuming there is “free/autonomous agency” of the sort Nietzsche thinks doesn’t exist.
Has certain normative content he doesn’t like (big disjunctive list)
Egalitarianism
High value on pity / altruism
Especially high value on happiness / low value on suffering
E.g. Nietzsche is a critic of utilitarianism, which might have some but not all of these features
Leitner calls Nietzsche a naturalist thinker about morality
Thinking of him in line with Hume and Freud, rather than the popular view of thinking of him as a precursor to postmodernism
“Naturalist” is a fraught term. Need to distinguish:
“substantive”
a certain ontological view (no ‘supernatural’ things exist)
“methodological”
an idea of how one does philosophy
There aren’t any distinctive philosophical practices, no difference in kind with other sciences (primarily psychology)
No reliance purely on a priori
Nietzsche is at least the latter. Calls himself the ‘first psychologist’
He is a ‘speculative methodological naturalist’ like Hume.
Same kind of structure of argument that is characteristic of Hume:
Take some class of beliefs (e.g. beliefs of morality)
Be skeptical that the beliefs can be rationally arrived at
Construct a psychological narrative for how we could have arrived at those beliefs / why they are attractive to human beings as they are.
E.g. in geneology of morals: how did the acetic ideal come to dominate the human mind / major religions.
How would Nietzsche. try to convince someone who believes in morality (in the pejorative sense)?
Leitner believes Nietzsche’s goal is not to get everyone to give up on morality.
“Herd morality for the herd”
There are different types of people
But there are (potential) creative geniuses like Goethe, Napoleon, Nietzsche himself, etc., whose flourishing is hindered by morality.
Lots of techniques to convince those people.
Nietzsche acknowledges that belief isn’t an entirely (or even mostly) rational deliberative process, so his methods of convincing are unusual compared to other philosophers.
Writes to ‘get you in the gut’ - is crude/rude/joking/hyperbolic.
“We don’t even notice the slave morality because it’s been victorious” He knows his readership isn’t even skeptical of morality, so he needs to be provokative to loosen them up / open them up to critical reflection.
Makes arguments
E.g. Naturalistic picture debunks common picture of human agency (his readership is becoming more committed to science, which allows him to draw up a tension)
But you can’t argue someone out of their morality, so rhetoric is important.
Nietzsche wants different moralities for different types of people, but maybe he’s implicitly arguing for a universal principle “what is good for people is good for their individual fluorishing as the type of person they are”
Distinguish two kinds of goodness
prudential goodness, what is good for an individual (e.g. their well-being)
moral goodness (all other types of goodness) (e.g. “morality in the pejorative sense ought be rejected because it prevents higher beings from flourishing”)
Nietzsche doesn’t believe these claims are ‘moral facts’ (he’s not a moral realist)
If a herd animal read Nietzsche’s book and understood it perfectly but reacted poorly (“but this criticism of herd morality isn’t good for the rest of of us”) … N would not think this person has made any error.
Nietzsche thinks it’s a matter of taste whether flourishing of higher beings is more important than well-being of the herd.
So he is not aiming for a universal principle that is in the best interest of everyone.
Leitner: I don’t think “analytic philosophy” exists, beyond some general stylistic concerns like attempting to be clear.
There is a current strand of moral philosophy intersecting with psychology that he would fit in with.
Nietzsche was a speculative naturalist, it’s possible that his beliefs that had empircal content are not psychological facts, but Leitner thinks after a century of psychological research that Nietzsche was right often.
E.g. he centred the role of the subconscious
Among the three dominant paradigms of moral psychology, Aristotle/Kant/Nietzsche, Nietzsche has the most plausible underlying assumptions given what we now know about psychology.
Personally sympathetic to anti-egalitarianism and reducing importance of agency by assigning strong roles to non-conscious factors.
Framing a philosophy in a non-universalizing way is
intellectually honest
easy to defend / hard to attack
suffers memetically (lacks a priori reason to convince anyone to adopt it) … so in some sense it cannot survive ‘at steady state’
October 1, 2009.
There has been historical precedent to place legal restrictions on human behavior due to disgust reaction
Rejection of something that is seen as a contaminant (useful in the context of feces, etc.). These are called the primary objects of disgust
In all societies, it gets extended in practice to groups of people seen as ‘low’/‘dirty’
extending the attributes of primary objects of disgust to these people, e.g. separate drinking fountains for blacks
Lord Devlin: a society needs to be able to defend itself against intrusion/defilement.
Justifies making things illegal even if they cause no harm to others
His rival: John Stuart Mill who said only harm to others should matter
More contemporarily, Leon Cass: disgust is a legitimate emotion which can sometimes guide us legitimately warn us of atrocity.
E.g. “torture” elicits disgust that rightly directs us away from it
When disgust is potent, we cannot rely on reasoning to give us respect.
Gays/Lesbians depicted as weirdos/animals
‘Torture’ also elicits indignation, which is a more constructive feeling towards righting the wrong of torture (concede that disgust happens to be right on this one)
That is wrong and it better not happen again
But maybe indignation may be argued to already be ‘getting too close’ - dignifying the abhorrent act with the status of “an act that is wrong” - maybe rejecting uncritically is the proper treatment?
“We won’t look at that at all” is evasion of moral confrontation.
Both have cognitive content and are falliable
Disgust’s validity limited to primary objects - which actually do pose a danger.
Juries to whom a murder is described in a more gory way are more likely to be harsher, even though this doesn’t always track how bad the homicide was / whether it was premeditated
Need to imagine the other as fully human like ourselves
Is this sufficient? Couldn’t a homophobe fairly imagine this but still conclude the other person is wrong?
Nussbaum: Certainly. Empathy is not sufficient for compassion.
perhaps not even necessary, e.g. compassion towards actual animals we cannot empathize with.
Should government be involved in marriage?
Marriage has three aspects:
Religious: state shouldn’t be involved (obviously)
Material: benefits given to certain relationships (civil unions sufficient)
Stuff in between: marriage is important because it signals some sort of societal approval of the act
Nussbaum doubts that this is really as true as proponents claim:
We don’t think of the state as supporting the N’th marriage of some celebrity
Extremely low bar in most states for being able to officiate a marriage
Civil unions analogous to transracial marriage:
People had to fight to not give this a different term since they truly believe it is equal
Three dimensions that get conflated:
Informational: the private is secret
Spatial: a private place, like the home
Decisional: what is private is yours to design
Example: pornography is legal, but only in your home. Or a court ruling that gay sex was legal unclear about whether it was merely because it was demonstrated in private that the homosexuality should be condoned.
Mill: self-regarding impact principle
What impact does this have on non-consenting strangers
Could recover our intuitions (the pornography has an impact on other people, acts in sex clubs that you have to voluntarily enter).
We should avoid the word ‘privacy’ because it’s such a nest of confusions.
- W/r/t torture + disgust + indignation:
- Agree that indignation comes off as more constructive than disgust, though is disgust an essential / primary cause for the indignation? Who is indigant about torture but not disgusted by it?
- Agree disgust is valid when it directs us away from danger
- Though Nussbaum's opponents are claiming homosexuality is a (societal) danger (for which disgust is just one piece of 'evidence'), so it's deflecting the main argument.
- A couple examples of disgust getting it wrong not convincing.
- Could come up with examples of indignation getting it wrong according to Nussbaum herself.
- Hypothetical: suppose Native Americans were disgusted by European settlers and were motivated to unify and reject the invasion. Wouldn't this have saved their society? Was a (counterfactual) stronger disgust reaction the only plausible hope for this happening?
- Is not eliciting disgust in nonconsenting strangers bad by Mill's principle? Couldn't there exist a country whose population is so vicerally disgusted by homosexuality that, in that country, it truly is wrong to have gay marriage? (e.g. Islamic country)
November 2, 2009.
What is interesting about perception for philosophers (distinct from biologists/neuroscientists)?
Perception has necessary role within analysis of certain concepts
Empirical facts about perception may be useful, and the physical theories of perception need not be challenged
E.g. gestalt psychology could be important to phenomonology
Notion of ‘perceptual features’. Empirical question:
Is it that to perceive is, essentially, to perceive objects? Every perception is a perception of something?
alternatively, we could also perceive ‘features’, too
More generally, is perception uniform or is there a richness/complexity of kind in the types of perception? This could influence philosophers who need to discuss the uses of perception.
In some sense, this is just a boring/trivial question about the grammar of perception.
Interesting empirical question: what is the privileged form of perceputal sensations - how far are we (always) breaking down sense data into objects? What physical mechanism does this?
Philosophy should disentangle confusions that arise out of the natural usage of the term.
An enduring example confusion:
Tendancy to approach problems in perception from a theory of knowledge.
How much do we know given our perceptions?
How does the knowledge from perceptions interact with other sources of knowledge?
This is often a confusion
(though may make sense in certain contexts, e.g. wondering if I’ve seen you before in the street)
It makes us wrongly think of the essence of perception as being in contact / direct relation with the world, as a means of getting knowledge.
This is a category error
Epistemologists are not actually dealing with perception, rather something derived from perception
Seeing something far away might be misleading
Two people could perceive the same phenomenon differently for various reasons
It’s a mistake of philosophers to lift this to questioning perception in general, questioning whether we ever could be in contact with the real world.
Raw data (waves/beams) impinge upon us, our minds make sense of this
Optics / biology outside domain of philosophy.
Then philosophy asks the trancendental question “how is it possible for us to access the outside world?”
From what point of view is this question being asked?
“Contact” is a better word than “access” because the fact that we (in the world) are in contact with the world is obvious and nullifies the philosophical question.
This question is a symptom of philosophy since Descartes, implies one has already gone astray from understanding what perception is.
Benoist would respond to a Cartesian skeptic differently; rather, would reject the question as ill-founded because the fact we are in contact with the world is presupposed before asking more abstract/higher order questions.
The fact that Descartes creates this artificial question leads him to the artificial separation of the physical and spiritual world. Both artificialities are related.
It’s fundamental to perception that it’s not possible to ‘take distance’ from perception
(yes, epistemlogically, but that is really treating the uses of perceptions).
It’s legitimate inquiry into the role of perception among other aspects of reasoning, but it is not about perception itself.
How does belief in raw contact with the world explain different observers observing the same thing differently?
E.g. “jaundiced eye” seeing the world with yellow tint
Benoist: perception is clearly dependent on where you are
The fact it is perspectival does not take away from the fact we are in direct contact
However we also have different faculties which cause differences beyond geometry (diseases, enhancements).
The yellow of jaundiced eye is just as much a reality and fact of perception as seeing a stick broken in the water.
There is a temptation to think when our perspective has dramatically affected the experience of some aspect of reality (stick), that it’s no longer the stick which we are perceiving
(even though it is the stick, even if it looks different than how we’re used to it - it’s just the reality of optics that viewed a certain way the experience of a stick is broken)
JL Austin: does anyone expect a stick, if it’s actually straight, has to appear to be straight under all circumstances?
It is wrong of philosophers to conclude from examples like this that our subjectivity is in between us and contact with reality.
Our subjectivity is just us being ourselves as we are in relation to the reality.
Subjectivity just captures the factors of perception which are dependent on the perceiver’s location/faculties
Subjectivity is just one aspect of the reality of perception (direct contact with the world).
December 1, 2009.
It’s an alternative source of evidence towards philosophical theses. - It’s not always meant to undermine traditional (armchair / mathematical) philosophy.
Philosphers use “our intuitions” as evidence for a compatibilist view
Among all our externally determined actions, they need to identify a subset of them as “free” - meaning things for which people can be credited/praised/blamed for.
Our concept of “freedom” is compatible with our concept of “externally caused”
To demonstrate this, they use a thought experiment, but empirically we find that the result of that experiment by varying trivial details - calls into doubt whether the thought experiment was only convincing to a biased group of people.
We tend to believe people can be held accountable when the stakes are higher (the thought experiment example action is trivial => people conclude determinism, the action is something heinous => people conclude compatibilism)
Why do we care what laypeople think over professional philosophers? Are philosophers biased away from the truth? Aren’t we learning about what people say rather than what really is? 1. We’re supplementing traditional philosophy - we want to show philosophical conclusions are not at odds with reality (we at least need an account in light of the evidence, e.g., above) 2. Laypeople lack prior theoretical commitments to bias them. 3. A general psychological investigation into how we draw conclusions from evidence (what biases are at play when we go data -> theory) is precisely what philosophy has always done. - We can learn how to do philosophy better by understanding, e.g., that we are likely to draw certain conclusions given our human desire to punish. - Some of our theories are an expression of current cultural identity rather than universal truth
This is in line with Nietzsche’s geneology of morality, which leads to severe relativism. Is this a natural consequence?
Experimental philosophy is neutral - people disagreeing about morality is evidence for our knowledge of morality rather than evidence for it being relative
Arguments about morality that are based on people sharing intuitions however could be invalidated/validated based on the evidence.
Utilitarians may have conclusions that can be demonstrably against layperson ethical intuitions, but they can have independent arguments for why they are still right and our intuitions are wrong.
Do we have faculties that trancend experience?
Empiricists see a continuity between what we observe and how we reason
Hume argues that we “think in pictures” and arrives at this conclusion by personal reflection.
Rationalists like Descartes says we can conceive of distinct figures of 1000 vs 999 sides, even if they are visually indistinguishable.
This point could be resolved by traditional psychology.
January 4, 2010.
Something is not acceptable because it is ‘not natural’.
This has counterexamples in both dimensions (good things - e.g. medicine - that are unnatural)
More sophisticated version: something that comes out of evolution is good
Good for survival is not the same as good in the ethical sense, even if the origins of our ethical norms came out of some competitive advantage it gave early humans.
What is good is indexed to the kind of thing one naturally is - We should always ask the question “is X good for Y” (rather than simply “Is X good?”) - “What is good for a plant is not good for what is good for a human”
It is still desirable to appeal to “Good simpliciter”. which is not of the form “Good for X”.
“What’s good for the Russian mafia is not good (simpliciter)”
Could argue the latter good is talking about “good for general community”
It is intelligible to ask “can we improve our natures?”
Difficult to appeal to our natures to explain how change our nature
We might actually be imagining some portion of our nature being fixed while varying a small part.
Evolutionary theory says natures change over time. So what is one appealing to?
You can take a ‘snapshot’ of a couple generations
We have an easy route to relieve ‘tension’ on the word “good” by adding an extra degree of freedom to it (what would otherwise a contradiction is no longer once I create multiple “kinds of goods”.
This gives you too many degrees of freedom - everything is good for some purpose for some kind of being, and we now need to prevent this from being abused by finding a principled reason for limiting whaat kinds of good are important in ethical normative judgments (“sure, you’re ‘good’ in some sense, but I will judge you”).
Seems like some form of “good (simpliciter)” can build in enough flexibility to account for all of the specific kinds of good (and any ‘global’ things too). When someone talks about “good for X” they are restricting our focus to a subset of the overall logic that is relevant for X, which could be useful since it’s a much simpler concept to worry about.
To claim there is no “good simpliciter” is to say that you can partition the logic of “good simpliciter” into the relevant subclasses (then by occams razor, the global good is not conceptually necessary).
February 12, 2010
Study of traits shaped by natural selection
No formal distinction from evolutionary biology
Example psychological traits/behaviors: jealousy, homicide, male promiscuity
What was its evolutionary function of jealousy? (studied by Bus)
Mate-guarding behavior. If you spend lots of resources/time on offspring, you want to make sure they’re yours.
Observed in primates standing in front of their mates and chasing off all other suitors
How to validate this hypothesis?
There are two claims to be tested empircally :
The existance of jealous mental states caused people to leave more offspring
Those offspring inherited the tendency to have jealous mental states
Couldn’t you just make up a narrative for any trait? - It is fair to accuse EP of making ‘just so’ plausible stories. - Though unfair to say there is anything wrong with that, even if it can be used to justify any conclusion. - Hypotheses (in general) have this feature as well. - We could’ve come up with a hypothesis for why the sky is black. - EP has been unfairly criticized for ‘just so’ stories when they are widespread in science. - However need to be careful to resist seduction of hearing a ‘just so’ story and think that the hypothesis is confirmed. - Admits that EP are more likely to succumb to this seduction over other fields - The narrative ought just the beginning of a research programme to verify it.
Can’t do tests on humans (ethical reasons, lifespan too long to measure reproductive success)
Mental states do not leave fossils
Need to make claims about proto-humans.
There is tendancy of (moral/political/mind) philosphers to bring in evolution as a skyhook for their theories
It’s not usually a core argument, but it’s used as support
They usually not good support because EP is almost never empirical
Furthermore, lots of evidence of evolutionary selected features that are selected for ‘arbitrary’ reasons, unrelated to flourishing
E.g. female preferring mate to have a particular spot pattern/chirp just due to ‘how they’re wired’ / randomness
So evolutionary fitness of a moral trait is not a good supporting argument by itself
March 4, 2010.
What are examples of metaphor?
Need to be careful to not use
‘dead metaphors’
idioms
“bit the dust” / “went west” / “bought the farm” -> die
Metaphors are devices for saying something and using something else
There are two lines of questions:
Technical ones in the philosophy of language (e.g. Joseph Stern)
Aesthetic questions (this is what Ted is interested in)
Metaphors are small-scale works of art
you need imaginative capacity to make/understand one
Art: the thing we do that we don’t need to do
it’s the place human’s exhibit their freedom
Once you understand a statement as ironic, it’s not hard to figure out what it means.
Could recognize something as a not-literal metaphor but then be puzzled about what it means
Try reading Wallace Stevens poetry as an example
Song of Solomon in the bible actually about sex, though you could read it without realizing that.
Is it possible to say what a metaphor says literally? Is this committing the ‘heresy of paraphrase’?
The question was confused. Metaphors aren’t reducible to similes which have a straightforward content. (“juliet is the sun” is not “juliet is like the sun”)
The simile is not true, there’s no relevant property shared by juliet and the sun that romeo means.
Inverse: “My love is like a red, red rose” why not “My life is a red, red rose”?
These questions are addressed by Joseph Stern, from analysis of the context.
In using a metaphor you will do something you couldn’t do otherwise, harder to say if you will say something you couldn’t do otherwise
Poetry is often the desire to compress a language and squeeze out all you can get
Can you translate poetry?
Of course.
Czech poet, Anschel, makes his name easier one day as Ansel, then much later writes under anagram “Selam”. Has a poem “Death Fugue” which begins “Der Tod ist ein Meister aus Deustchland”
Should be translated “Death is a Meister from Germany” because no subtitutee would work for Meister.
Romans made very few advances in mathematics, possibly because their notation was so bad.
Representation makes a big difference in our ability to imagine
This may be analogous to poetry which represents concepts in a way that prose may not be able to.
We must be free, but if we’re free then there’s chaos and we end up not free, so the solution is a self-imposed constraint.
Related vaguely.
Interpreting metaphors in the same way seen as a means of connecting with other people (meaningful because it is falliable)
Wittgenstein in PI: “Sometimes people we cannot find our feet with them”
If you tell a joke that someone laughs at, you find youself in that person. Gratifying.
If you tell a joke that someone doesn’t laugh at, we react poorly, like something has gone wrong.
Irony/metaphors/jokes. All ways we live within but break rules. They help us get in touch with our freedom.
Are inappropriate/offensive jokes similar in how they work to normal jokes? Or has something gone wrong?
Cohen: they’re the same. Learning to not say telling offensive jokes is akin to learning to not pinch a stranger or roughhouse with someone who doesn’t want to.
Double infliction: they don’t like it, then you say they don’t have a sense of humor (it’s their fault for not finding it funny)
They don’t need a justification to not find it funny.
No moral theories could account for why it’s not ok for a stranger to say “I don’t like it when you cross your legs” but ok to say “Your music is too loud”. It’s something to be negotiated - you won’t learn it studying moral philosophy. The layperson is equally or more qualified than the philosopher at these practical questions.
No bearing on the functioning of the joke among people who find it funny.
Would need some account of it being harmful, that it perpetuates or creates harmful stereotypes has not been convincingly shown
The fact that a stereotype isn’t true is not a mark against the joke (a joke is always a small fiction)
“Not everything you don’t like is immoral”
April 5, 2010
Distinction: good (absolutely) vs good for something vs good
E.g. It’s good to be kind, it’s good for me to study math, that’s a good car
British 20th centurary moral philosophers like GE Moore don’t like “good for X” wanting a morality that is not egoistic, instead trying to frame in terms of absolute good.
These theories overlooked possible justifications which use “good for” but are not egoistic.
Absolute good is a much more abstract / questionable concept, so it would be nice to frame ethics without it if possible.
These may be different (absolute good is incoherent, but not absolute bad) but Kraut needs neither.
It’s coherent to say “pain is bad”, but we also say “it’s bad for me to feel pain”. What more is gained by using absolute language?
What about cruelty/cowardice?
Again we can show that these things are bad because they are bad for people.
Does this point of view lead to egoism, e.g. good/bad being instrumental to what we want?
Mistake to conflate “good for me” as “what I want” or “good for some end I want”.
There are objective truths of what is good for certain types of beings, even if we’re ignorant.
There are differences and similarities for what is good for different people/species.
Cannot apply same formula to each case.
What problems does thinking about morality in terms of absolute good have?
It’s not necessarily bad. But it could be used to justify something that is bad for everybody.
Argument against euthansisa: life itself is good (would not be sufficient if Kraut’s thesis is accepted)
E.g. good for A to be loud, good for B to be in quiet environment
We should organize political institutions to avoid needless conflict.
The concept of justice is needed to resolve these cases.
“Absolute Good” not needed
We can frame some instances of absolute good/bad in terms of good for, but the interesting question is can this be done for all uses?
if absolute bad exists, then it does seem possible that an institituion/relationship is good for everyone involved but still is bad (or vice versa). E.g. euthansia.
Kraut’s grammar of moral terms should not alter this fact.
May 7, 2010.
Wittgenstein opens PI Augustine’s picture:
Common sense description: words name objects, sentences are combinations of such names
Every word has a correlated meaning which is the object for which the word stands.
Problem: what object does the word ‘and’ stand for?
Standard thought is this picture is the main object of criticism of PI
Gustafsson thinks this is making too much philosophy out of the Augustinian picture.
(in fact, Augstine himself doesn’t subscribe to the philosophical implications commonly attributed to the passage)
This simple picture is attractive and can be applied in good ways or bad ways.
Pictures for Wittgenstein operate on a primative level, can’t say they’re right or wrong.
Wittgenstein in Foundations of Mathematics: “We don’t judge the picture but we judge by means of the picture.”
They are prototheories / paradigms that are bad if cut from their useful applications.
e.g. Start looking for the correlate of the word red, postulate Platonic forms and get philosophical confusion
Cannot be argued against because counterexamples can be absorbed by a picture, which can be elaborated upon
The closer the picture is to a fully fleshed out theory, the harder (more artificial-seeming) this becomes.
If Wittgenstein is not strictly criticizing Augustine, is he at least criticizing Plato?
Wittgenstein quotes Theatetus picture of language: Socrates is presenting something he has heard and he concludes we don’t really understand it.
Wittgenstein considers himself in a common struggle with Plato and Augustine. He is attracted by these pictures but is trying to overcome them, just like Plato and Augustine.
If Wittgenstein is documenting his personal struggles, then what philosophical value is there? Is it just of autobiographical interest?
There are many levels of PI - he provides arguments and uncovers paradoxes.
Is he merely providing more details to the pictures in order to try to avoid the counterexamples/paradoxes? Is he trying to get rid of pictures altogether? Experts are divided.
Some say ‘meaning as use’ is a picture, one he thinks is less harmful than augustinian view
He doesn’t really want to construct theories, but rather wants philosophical peace / quietism.
thinking as something that goes on inside your head
regarding infinity as merely something very large
June 3, 2010.
Contexualism concerns the truth of an utterance of depending on factors outside of the statement itself.
There is a spectrum of statements one can acknowledge as contexual:
At one extreme, statements like “I am cold”
The truth is obviously contexually dependent on the speaker of the utterance.
Mary wins $1 million in lottery
Deedee says that Mary is rich now
Naomi (who is wealthier) says “No, Mary is not rich.”
We want to say Deedee and Naomi are both speaking “truth” and need an account.
Relevant contextual parameter: the standard of wealth according to the speaker.
Contextualist says: because the conversational standards for deploying “rich” vary among Deedee’s community and Naomi’s community, the truth conditions of their utterances should also vary.
The bank case:
On Friday, a man and his wife go to the bank and see a long line. The man says “Oh well we can go tomorrow” and asked how he knows, he says “I was here last Saturday and they were open.”
Alternate scenario, it’s really impt that they deposit their check. He is asked “how do you really know? Maybe they changed their hours.” and he updates “You know, you’re right, I don’t know.”
Contextualist wants to say “I know X” and “I don’t know X” were both truthful utterances with no change in world state (but rather, what changed was the context-dependent truth conditions)
Epistemological contextualists claim that the standard for knowing X is dependent on what doubts have been raised in a conversation (the doubts become ‘live’). Skepticism is addressed because we can hand the skeptic a victory in their ivory tower (you are right that we don’t know anything) while denying the skeptic the right to challenge an ordinary person living their life claiming to know many things.
Counterpoint: why were hyperbolic doubts even raised? Actually, the skeptics were concerned with ordinary claims of knowing.
Contextualists could be said to be using some motivated reasoning to insulate ordinary belief from what goes on in the phil seminar room.
A more radical example is Pia and the maple tree.
The spectrum could be said to correspond to a belief in a ‘core/unchanging’ content of a word/sentence (meaning that is purely based on the definitions of the words) and people arguing how big that core should be. - “The cat is on the mat” - which cat may change on context, etc. but there is something unchanging; we cannot mean “The dog is in the air.” - Those who disagree have to explain how do we understand each other at all. - Some radical contextualists don’t say that for all X Y, X can mean Y. But just that forall utterances X, there is an indefinite number of meanings that are consistent with that utterance (there are also an indefinite number of meanings that are inconsistent.
The principle: that there is a kind of content of an utterance which is tied to the point of the utterance (which is tied to motivations/expectations of conversational participants).
This is an underlying assumption of many contextualist arguments.
The point of Naomi’s utterance is different (to relate Mary’s wealth to the standards of wealth in her world).
Unfounded: context principle justifies tying the truth conditions to points/interest/conversational standards.
Counterexample: wealthy people who say they themselves aren’t wealthy - it is in their interests to not seem wealthy (to avoid legislation, to seem like a salt-of-earth person). Perhaps their use of the word is serving those desires.
The truth conditions ought to float free of the ‘local discourse’ if the argument actually concerns disputed territory. If Deedee/Naomi agree that the rich ought pay a special tax, then it is crucial to have a notion of ‘rich’ that is dictated by a larger discourse which includes both participants (the larger community agrees with Deedee in this case, so Naomi’s claim can be called false even if it matches her local community’s use of the word).
Contextualists acknowledge that interests/focus of attention vary among people but do not pay special attention to what those interests are - harsh charge but evidence by the fact that most contextualists are not methadological contextualists
(Wittgenstein was a methodological contextualist).
The ‘freighted terms’ which philosophers are most often interested in seem to more likely be the cases like ‘wealth’ where we do not want to let people’s biases dictate the correctness of their word usage.
July 9, 2010.
A formal theory characterizing various ways to combine individual beliefs into collective beliefs
What could it mean for a group to have beliefs over and above the beliefs of the individuals?
We ascribe beliefs in order to interpret actions/decisions based on reasons
Groups act and make decisions based on reasons, so it seems reasonable to think that we can ascribe beliefs to groups
The group beliefs are uniquely determined by the individuals’ beliefs, but it may not be identical to any of the individuals.
Example: condo asssociation where 50% believe \(A\) and 50% not \(A\). Maybe it’s reasonable to ascribe an indeterminate belief towards \(A\), but none of the individuals is indeterminate.
This is important because we want to know how we should revise our beliefs due to a group testimony.
What if we say the ‘group believes’ what the majority of the group believes? - Problem: majorities are not consistent over multiple beliefs IF the beliefs are logically connected. - 51% of people believe \(P\), 51% believe \(Q\), 1% believe \(P\land Q\). - Under this proposal, the majority has inconsistent beliefs (and therefore believes everything) - Real example: - German politicians voted on the the three propositions: - Should Berlin or Bohn be the capital? - Should the parliament be in Berlin or Bohn? - Should the capital be where parliament is?
Supermajority:
If you construct threshold carefully enough, you can guarantee consistency
With \(P\land Q\) example, you need 2/3.
Determine ahead of time, determine what are most important (logically independent) propositions, use inference to determine the rest of propositions.
Research in the field isn’t really about finding specific alternatives:
Actual goal: formalize the desiderata and find out which sets of constraints are compatible with each other.
Mathematically provable that we can’t satisfy a bunch of desiderata simultaneously.
However, one particular constraint both causes a lot of problems and really isn’t that justified: the independence constraint
The collective belief on a particular proposition is uniquely determined by opinions of the members of the group on that belief alone.
Our intuitive sense of collective belief is sensitive to the reasons for belief.
Example:
Two panels: all believe that government and parliament should be in same city, also all believe it should be in Berlin. Other is split on which city things should be on, but all believe it should be in same city.
Independence would say that both panels agree ‘equally’ on whether government+parliament should be in same city.
Intuitively we know that the second group has undermining/inconsistent reasons for their agreed-upon belief, so their aggregate belief should be strictly weaker than first panel.
Independence is usually involved in the unsatisfiable subsets of constraints.
In practice, we recognize different judgment aggregation strategies are appropriate in different scenarios
But this isn’t a satisfying resolution in itself; we need to better understand what makes certain desiderata appropriate for a given situation.
August 2, 2010.
Example: I know there is a table in front of me (both sides agree: if I know anything, I at least know that)
Skeptic rejects that, and therefore rejects that you know anything
Many different skeptical arguments, often of the form “There exists a scenario in which you are having the same phenomenological experience yet there is no table, so how can you know whether you are in that scenario vs the genuine experience scenario?”
Examples: dreaming, evil genius, brain in vat (Putnam)
Logical priority of conventional methods of determining thoughts over brain scanner
There is a causal dependence between brain activity and experience, but it is a leap to suggest that we can identify brain activity with experience.
Even if we found an incredible empirical correlation between brain activity and experience, if we suddenly had a conflict one day (brain scanner says that the subject thinks he’s drinking coffee, but we see him eating ice cream and he assures us he knows/believes he is eating ice cream), then we would conclude the brain scanner is wrong, not the
What it means to be a thought is not the same thing as what it means to be a brain state
Brain states connected by casual relationships. Cannot be ‘correct’ or incorrect.
Mental states occupy the space of reasons - the meaning of certain thought is identified by its relationships to other thoughts. Structured by normative relationships (can be correct or incorrect).
If brain scanner with amazing correlation says that someone is telling a lie by analyzing brain states, they may be lying 100% of the time that brain scanner says they’re lying, but it is not the brain state itself that makes them lying or not.
Drawing from thoughts of John MacDowell (“Mind and World”)
For a thought to be ‘about’ an object (world-directed, with empirical content) - it’s necessary that the correctness of the thought to be answerable to how things are.
For an intention to be an intention - it has to determine the correctness/incorrectness of some subsequent action.
A brain is not logically answerable to reality and is not overtly acting in the world, so it’s not fair to say it has thoughts or intentions.
This is not a general anti-skeptic argument, but other skeptical tactics might be addressable by similar reasoning.
Thus, Edward is proposing bottom up anti-skepticism, rather than some top-down “reason for knowing that the table is there”
Stanley Cavell has written well about how skeptical lines of thought arise naturally (i.e. they are not purely the product of academic philosophy).
Skepticism shows up in lots of fields/subfields of philosophy, and it’s important to prevent the confusion that arises here from spreading. (e.g. brain scanner is relevant in legal topics)
(written in 2018) - 1A: Logical priority of conventional methods of determining thoughts over brain scanner - Is this related to the fact that the brain scanner is purely correlation, rather than based on some fundamental theory? - If we had a more fundamental theory that the brain scanner’s workings fit in with (e.g. quantum mechanics), then we would be more likely to embrace the absurd scenario of the subject being insane (and/or we failed to identify his environment) rather than saying quantum mechanics is wrong. - Surely there are historical examples where X is a ground for some technique Y, but for various reasons eventually Y becomes ground for X? - Logically-prior = closer to the ‘center’ of the web-of-beliefs. - Furthermore, this example only works if it is possible that there is a conflict (in the world where there is perfect correlation, then we can identify brain activity with thoughts) - 1B: “To be a brain state is one kind of thing, to have a thought is a different kind of thing” - This is a good point towards saying they are not ‘literally’ identical, in the sense of “My dad’s wife” and “My mom” being literally ‘different’ (they have different truth conditions) but may be equivalent given some state of affairs. - This is perhaps sufficient to say “no reason to think brains in vats can think” … but at least it’s sufficient for “there is a reason to think brains in vats cannot think”. - What this argument does not show (which maybe Ed is advocating) is that it is incoherent to identify brain states with mental states. If we can identify them, then they both are both kinds of things and there are no - There may be an isomorphism between the “logical space of reasons” and the space of brain states related by physical causality. - If brain states (and their relations) were in bijective corrspondance to thoughts, then we can refer to a brain state by its thought and vice versa. Whether or not this is the case is precisely the debate at hand, but bringing this point up does not advance the argument one way or another. - How to decide whether to believe such an isomorphism likely exists is complicated. - 2: - The belief that there is a table in front of me (even in brain-in-vat scenario) IS answerable to reality (and the the belief is false). Likewise for intentions (the intention will be unfulfilled, unless one is desiring to be a brain in a vat) - How does this bear on the legality of killing comatose people (they are in an analogous situation)
September 8, 2010.
Why protect religious conscience, over and above other forms of moral conscience?
Historically, lots of religious intolerance have led to atrocities.
What’s distinctive of religious belief (not merely theistic religions)? Two characteristics:
There are certain beliefs that are insulated from ordinary standards of reasons and evidence.
This is trying to cache out “faith”
There are certain obligations that are demanded of a believer.
This is why religion comes in conflict with the law, so the need for practices
Potential counterexamples:
Not let in enough: Christian apologists willing to argue/defend Christiantity based on normal standards of evidence.
It’s true there exist intellectualist traditions within religious thought.
Most believers want their beliefs insulated
These are beliefs that are post-hoc rationalizations
Could say these are not religious hypotheses, although they deployed to support religion.
Let in too much: secular people have opinions about the meaning of life that are not subject to reason/evidence. E.g. John Lennon thinks we should give peace a chance, I’m commanded to not go to war.
Whether you think moral views are insulated from reasons/evidence depends on deeper metaphysical views.
Naturalistic moral realist: morality is just like science, so it is answerable to reasons and evidence
Noncognitivist: moral beliefs are actually expressing emotions, so not applicable to rule 1.
Neither of the distinctive characteristics are related to the standard arguments for tolerating religion.
Utilitarian and Rawlsian arguments justify protecting liberty of conscience but would not single out religion.
Nussbaum - doesn’t religion deserve more than toleration, e.g. respect:
Mere toleration: you disapprove but you have to put up with them.
Respect is ambiguous:
recognition respect: “you ought to respect his feelings”
respect for people in virtue of them being people
appraisal respect: “I respect her intellect”
admiration
People conflate 1 (which is uncontroversially owed to strangers), but bait-and-switch with meaning 2.
Nussbaum’s example: Roger Williams founded Rhode Island and discovered the native americans were more similar than he expected.
This still doesn’t justify appraisal respect.
Extend the practice of appealing for an exemption from a law to all matters of conscience.
Worrisome that courts will now have to judge whether matters truly are of conscience.
It’s easier to figure out if 1.) someone is a member of a religion, 2.) if a religion demands a certain behavior rather than to figure out if a person is being genuine.
Maybe pragmatic reasons for status quo, but not moral reasons.
October 6, 2010.
“Completing” the contract theory of justice started by Hobbes, developed by Locke / Rousseau / Kant.
Most influential modern political philosopher.
Most theories are contractural but not Sen’s.
Don’t think pursuit of justice involves looking for the perfectly just world.
Issues of injustice:
people who need medicine that can be cheaply produced
children not being educaiton
tons of other ways. Addressing these individually won’t create a perfectly just world
We can aspire to a perfectly just institution without guaranteeing a perfectly just world
The latter also depends on people’s behavior/natures.
E.g. if people are incorruptable, then more socially trusting institutions become feasible.
Seeking a perfect world will not help us rank all of the imperfect worlds we have as more promixate options.
Neither necessary nor sufficient to have a particular target.
Do we have no basis for saying something is unjust?
Example: you’re in a sauna and the temperature keeps going up. Once you feel in danger, you try to leave but the door is locked. Someone outside sees but can’t open the door either. But he does have access to the temperature control. You ask him to lower and he says “what is the ideal temperature you want” which you don’t know. He could object that without a principled goal, all there is arbitrary gut reaction (the point: gut reaction is important)
There are many kinds of justice, not a single scale:
Liberty, fairness, reducing inequality, removing poverty
For Rawls, these all matter but he strictly orders them in importance like above
More natural to trade off, like a small concession in liberty could be worth a huge reduction in poverty
Concern of advocating societal change without a goal: - E.g. “reduce inequality”, but if there is no stopping point, then this could head towards a situation worse than the current one (even if the current one has too much inequality).
November 8, 2010.
Action at a distance
E.g. Gravity/EM, something in one place can affect something far away without anything passing in between
Trying to explain how a magic trick (making a match levitate) works. 1. The magician has the power to make things levitate with their mind
This would be disturbing because it can’t be generalized / doesn’t fit into a universal scientific model
The magician has magnets in the walls and controls them with a small computer
Would alleviate the disturbance.
The magician can send out ‘levitator particles’ from the eyes. There’s a ‘levitator particle’ detector which is triggered, shows they have energy and can do work.
Would also alleviate the concern, the particles would become the new normal, a feature of the world.
Action at a distance would be like having no such explanation (though there is regularity/predictability).
Fear: if we allow action at a distance, then anything is permitted anywhere
Billiard ball motion could be determined by huge (far away) bodies of motion rather than anything local.
in 17th century, “mechanistic philosophy” (e.g. Boyle)
All explanations should be given by just matter and motion
Magnets thought to emit something similar to levitator particles
in 19th century, get the development of a field.
Newton’s gravity is action at a distance is already well-established
action at a distance now tolerated widely
Faraday/Maxwell are able to reform E&M that doesn’t require action at a distance, have nothing to say about gravity.
Einstein then gets rid of it for gravity
Einstein has methodological complaint. Science is impossible if objects aren’t independent of each other.
Leibniz Principle of Sufficient Reason: for everything that happens, there is a reason why it (in particular) happened.
Paramenides: nothing comes from nothing (apple comes from the tree, apple’s redness came from the seed (DNA))
Change is impossible follows from this
In some sense, something coming from nothing would violate the principle of sufficient reason.
Many arguments for and against.
Philosophically, one must have a framework to do science.
P.S.R. is really hard to do without.
There were never historically people who lamented loss of action at a distance when an equally predictive theory becomes available.
December 6, 2010.
This concerns the pragmatics of language
Social identities are skills, being a professor/parent is like dribbling a basketball
“Calls”
Say “Yo, Matt!” to someone in the street. Have recognized Matt as a social partner but also demands Matt recognize me.
“Performative” Difference between judge saying “the meeting is adjourned” vs someone outside looking in who tells someone “the meeting is adjourned”
“Order”
Unlike a call, it is an asymmetric speech action.
Responding acknowledges the power gradient.
Distinct from requests and treaties
If students respond to roll call, they are jointly bringing into being the roles of “teacher” and “student”
Gendered/Racial
We recognize demographics in certain ways.
Data shows people talk to male babies different from female babies
Data shows teachers let male students talk for longer before interrupting (even filtering for female Womens’ Studies profs)
You can refuse the way someone engages you, but is a tricky negotiation.
There’s no way to stay neutral - either have to be aggressive or passive (accept the role you don’t want to be placed in) .
A call can be responded to appropriately or inapprorpiate - placing someone in a role puts them in a normative role.
Example: school system in DC
Nominally egalitarian, however:
Good schools are in rich neighborhoods (issues with transportation)
Complicated application / interview process
Some identities seem chosen vs not
Not exactly a clear line (one chooses to work at a sweatshop, but the alternative was starving)
Big normative implications for roles that are perceived as a choice
The point of analyzing these social roles is to see where it’s possible to intervene
Certain problems are only addressible by social organizers
We can be more aware of how these roles affect our lives
A project of political liberation.
What’s a good reason to resist a social role?
No general answers - just good reasons for doing anything. E.g. freedom, prevention of human fluorishing.
January 12, 2011.
Information given to us via testimony vs sense experience
There are many situations where we trust and others where we distrust
Need to be able to benefit from communication with others.
Reductionist: Must have a reason to trust.
Anti-reductionist: We can trust testimony unless we have reason to distrust.
Counterpoint:
Our senses work to serve our interests. Others have their own interests.
One communicates with another to have an effect on them. Maybe this is benevolent, maybe it’s hostile.
Vigilance: on guard for interlocutors who don’t have our best interest at heart.
Analogy: we walk in a crowd without issue because everyone is vigiliant.
This would not be possible if we thought every stranger would completely ignore us.
So we need trust, but we are not paralyzed by consciously distrusting-by-default each stranger. The community vigilance is the solution.
How do we trust people without vigilance:
It’s possible, after all children do it.
However, at some point it will be in someone’s interest to deceive.
Communication is valuable because others are vigilant
There exist social costs to miscommunication / deception / cheating.
Descriptive questions too (not just normative)
What we do is close to the reductionist’s norm
Experimental psychology experiments
People encounter a new face and instantly look for trustworthiness
there is the least variation in ‘trustworthiness score’ (among other properties) when you vary the amount of time a subject has exposed to the picture
Children as young as 3 will trust the information from a ‘nice agent’ over a ’mean agent
However maybe life would be better if everyone trusted a littlee more (even if there were slight higher personal risks). Collective action problem.
Multiple independent sources of some belief reinforce strength of that belief.
Peer review system reflective of epistemic vigilance norms.
February 8, 2011.
Belief when you don’t have overwhelming evidence.
Something distinct from knowledge.
E.g. Faith in the goodness of humanity. Faith in the resurrection.
Two opinions: faith is a virtue, faith is intellectually irresponsible
What is the structure of the faith?
Recent interest in Paul:
Had a conversion from a persecutor of Christians. He doesn’t seek historical evidence for it.
After his revelation, he doesn’t go to Jerusalem, he goes into the desert.
He is not seeking prophetic evidence, yet it enables him to act in the world.
The structure of Paul’s faith is interesting. “Response to a call” as opposed to some concrete belief.
The formation of a self in relation to a call/ethical demand.
That call is going to motivate a self to act.
Relevance: there is a motivational deficit in liberal democracy, how to we remedy this?
The interesting part of religion is not whether their supernatural beliefs are true, rather how the call believers to action.
What sort of thing is commitment?
Something that is also touched upon in Existentialist philosophy too.
Moral athiests could deny that they take things on faith.
Critchley thinks ‘evangelical athiests’ (Dawkins/Hitchens).
Faith in reason, that science will work out the truths of the universe without participating.
In Sermon on the Mount, Jesus says to love your enemy and to have infinite forgiveness.
You can think Jesus was entitled to make these demands because he was God.
Alternatively he was just some crazy guy making extreme demands to prick people’s conscience.
Passive nihilism comes out of people being distanced/austerity towards moral commitment.
Reason/rationality cannot be divorced from processes like bureaucracy of modernity. Need faith / commitment to overcome sorts of bad rational processes.
How to choose the right commitment?
E.g. want to avoid becoming committed Nazis.
Commitment + generality/universality (Kantian)
Need practical moral philosophy to popularize something abstract like Kantian morality.
Friendship and Love
These require trust/faith (Othello example)
Friendship: Aristotelian vs Christian views
A liberal society based on reason would require a private/public separation
Anarchism has a variety of alternatives of new forms of order.
March 7, 2011.
What does “liberalism” refer to?
Used in such a wide variety of senses that it means almost nothing at all now.
Not useful to use the term to think about society or use as a normative concept
A historical approach to the term is valuable
The result of a large tradition of different components fusing together
After many things have fused together (by convenience) it looks like they come together by necessity
This makes the whole framework seem self-evident, which is convenient for your political system to have
E.g. democracy and liberalism seem like they belong together
liberalism has toleration as a core principle
democracy has no such commitment - you could vote to ostracize someone people don’t like.
democracy doesn’t like elections.
Another strand: voluntaryness better than force
Another strand: fear of concentrated power
Another strand: individual > group
Another strand: laissez faire capitalism
Two components of liberalism Geuss is worried about
Neutrality
There is no notion of ‘neutrality’ that is both weak enough to be a sensible notion as well as strong enough to do the normative job liberals want it to do
Neutrality itself cannot be a generator of political value
Consensus
It’s not that lack of consensus is good and it’s good to push people around
Rather, consensus must be treated as an empirical concept
As opposed to a ‘necessary condition of society’ - that’s not true
Making it this weak would be vacuous; would allow one to say “members of concentration camps were in a consensus with their guards, as they formed a social system”
Moving to a more realistic/empirical notion, e.g. everyone checking off the same box in the voting booth, this doesn’t have any normative power
There’s a feeling that every disagreement can be resolved to consensus.
It isn’t proven that it’s always possible, nor if it is possible that it’s good.
Kant argues that we have a natural tendency to overgeneralize from experience
E.g. We see things in our life have causes, and then think everything has a cause, which leads to the concept of God
Likewise, the belief that everything can be resolved by consensus fits this pattern.
This is part of the plausibility of liberalism:
I like to be free, I don’t like to be pushed around, I like us to be in consensus (this is fine)
Now jump to saying this can be done for the whole world
This can’t be taken for granted.
Is the above an accusation that liberalism is hypocritical?
E.g. America was based on consensus while nonconsensually displacing native americans.
Geuss:
‘hypocrisy’ is too strong of a term, which implies a conscious duplicitousness
Human beings are self-centered (we see ourselves as more central than we actually are, want to see ourselves as good) which is at odds with liberal ideal
Should we make incremental adjustments vs revolution to fix liberalism?
Geuss: keen on preserving our abilities to imagine utopias.
We can transform some of those aspirations into practical action.
There is a gap betweeen action and imagination.
Pragmatists eliminate that gap, ‘reduce’ imagination just to action.
Nothing wrong with aspirations that are not immediately realized - they can remain in the culture until they are realized.
So we can pursue both the immediate and more radical changes.
What role is there for art to play in developing our political imagination?
Escaping from politics is a kind of politics, after all
Escape because politics at the moment is intolerable/unworkable.
Two ways:
Political novels like Flaubert’s Salembot
descriptions of radically different worlds
having an imaginative picture of a particular world makes us relate to our own reality differently
Norm-breaking poetry, like Paul Celan:
Language rules are oppressive, conformist
Use words in different ways to break stifling forms of everyday speech
April 6, 2011.
Can a group of people do an action?
We regularly conjoin plural subjects with action verbs.
We have a desire to analyze the collective action purely into terms of the individual actions. This is a mistake - removes what is interesting about collective action.
Example: five people building a wall
Someone could say there is no more to this action than just the individuals laying bricks / cement.
This account gives no relations between the people doing the various actions
Example: swedish diplomat
Case 1: collective action
Want to talk to the diplomat, who is talking to someone else. Your teammate engages the other person, opening up the diplomat for you to sweep in.
Together you pull off the plan together
Case 2: no collective action
Same as above, except no coordination was planned with the teammate
It just happens that this other person started talking to the person talking to the diplomat, and you seize the opportunity.
It’s just one agent exploiting the actions of another agent.
The reduction of group actions to individual actions cannot distinguish the two cases.
One source of pressure that makes people (illegitimately) doubt the reality of collective action:
Cause by an intuitive (but bad) picture of how solitary action happens
A process that is caused by a psychological state
When we generalize this to groups, it requires us to postulate a group mind.
Laurence: this picture is bad because it presupposes the causality between action and mental states is like the causality between rocks bumping each other.
Different kinds of explanation ought be appropriate for talking about human action.
It lacks any reference to people’s purposes for acting.
Alternative
Slogan: acting together is acting with a common purpose.
E.g. bank robber is listening to a stethescope
We can ask why and get the answer “to crack the safe”
We can ask why is he cracking the safe and get the answer “because the robbers are robbing the bank”
Isn’t this circular?
All that was presupposed was that an intentional action with a plural subject is intelligible.
Proof: Laurence can articulate the difference between actions with plural subjects and plural agents
Why is the gunman holding the gun on the security guard? To immobilize him? Why? Because the robbers are robbing the bank.
What it means for the two actors to be acting together is that the “purposive explanations” of their actions unify at some point.
Ethical/political consequences
Individualistic picture of acting together can cause problems
E.g. understanding democratic reasoning in terms of a lone agent tries to satisfy his preferences will cause distortions
What goes missing is the notion of a shared purpose/mission
Will be difficult to reconstruct the group from the individual citizen’s purposes.
Situations where impermissible coercion is involved
“Jump through this hoop or else I’ll set your pants on fire”
Force used against free riders (e.g. taxation)
Without collective reasons, we end up with strong libertarian arguments that taxation is theft.
My response:
Why is the reduction to individuals ‘a mistake’? Agree that it’s not the only way to make sense of a collective action, e.g. I can think of a person as a person or as a collection of atoms. The existence of one (even one that is strictly ‘more fundamental’) doesn’t render other interpretations incorrect?
May 17, 2011
“How possible” questions
General form: X makes Y seem impossible, yet nevertheless Y is possible.
Can’t we just reject X because we take Y to be possible, which contradicts taking X seriously?
Y=“how is freedom possible?”
X = “we are chemical/physical beings”
“how is knowledge of the external world possible?”
X = skepticism “How do you know you’re not dreaming / in the Matrix?”
you don’t independently know that you’re not in the Matrix / brain in the vat, so how could you know that your hand is in front of you?
The skeptic has put an insuperable requirement for knowledge of the external world
Two possible replies:
Say the requirement is not genuine
More promising since requirements are usually designed to be unfulfillable (though they still are very compelling)
Challenge the word “independently”
challenging skeptic’s assumed notions of epistemic priority because you are accused of question begging if you say “I know I have a hand, so therefore I’m not a handless brain in a vat”
GE Moore strategy: argue from knowledge to knowledge rather from ignorance to ignorance.
Say we can satisfy the requirement
Sherlock Holmes meets you for the first time and says “ah I see you’re from NJ”. “how did sherlock holmes know this?”
X = “given that I didn’t do anything to reveal my origin”
Kant, ‘grandfather of how possible questions’ and inventor of trancendental arguments
How is mathematical knowledge possible? How is pure science possible?
For the former, Kant answers by drawing attention to how diagramatic reasoning is crucial.
One can respond to how diagrams (with, say, specific triangles) could prove general properties (e.g. about triangles in general) and Kant has a response.
He’s not asking from an epistemological perspective.
These are interesting b/c they are examples of synthetic a priori
How is that kind of knowledge possible? (given that it must be possible in virtue of mathematical knowledge existing)
X = “where does the knowledge come from if not experience nor analysis of concepts?”
Trancendental argument:
start off with assumption we have a certain experience, then try to find necessary conditions for us to have that experience
E.g. external world skeptics believe we have inner experience. Kant argues that outer experience is a necessary precondition for inner experience. Therefore we have knowledge of the external world.
This doesn’t answer the ‘how possible’ question. It shows that Y is true but does not dissolve the obstacle X. So again we have something that seems necessarily true that asserts something that’s possible is impossible. The skeptic has the upper hand since their arguments aren’t as abstract / untrustworthy.
But it’s not like Kant thinks his trancendental arguments were designed to answer his ‘how possible’ questions (some commentators make the mistake of assuming this).
June 21, 2011.
Is hearing emotion in music a purely cultural convention?
Distinguish two quesitions
Whether culture has impact on the perceptual states from hearing pieces of music
Whether on a partiuclar occasion of hearing music, the perception depends on cultural
The perception being dependent on cultural factors doesn’t mean it can’t be considered perceptual
E.g. language (clearly culture-dependent) where the words perceived have meanings
E.g. you hear/perceive “snow” as meaning (the explanation why that in particular is the case involves culture) but the perception itself is not cultural.
With music, it’s not interesting to trace the causal origins of the perceptual state but the nature of the perceptual state itself / what it is for it to have emotional content.
Three fundamental different experiences
See something a certain way (see an apple as an apple)
See something as a representation of something else (picture of an apple)
“Metaphorical seen-as”
“Juliet is the sun” - linguistic metaphors are just a specific instance of a general mental state of metaphorical thinking.
Others attempts to reduce this type of thinking to other kinds of mental states unsatisfactory.
Music Examples:
Des Prex, Ave Maria: lyrics involve “universe filling up gladness”, and you hear the music as filling up space.
Debussy,L’Voiles or Le catedrale engloutie: can perceive the fluttering sails and sinking cathedral.
Distinction between imagining X as Y and phenomonologically perceiving X as Y (example of Still life with pots (Zurbarán) that you really directly see as people, vs forcing yourself to imagine four things on the table as people).
Phenomologically distinct from actually thinking the pots are people or even depictions of people.
Explanation of this
“isomorphism” (Kris: actually should just be (homo)morphism)
Basically an analogy.
Changes in pitch and speed map onto changes in speed of the wind.
There are tons of these that are possible, but not all are “psychologically real”
Minor chord has negative affect due to its relation to major chord.
Why is it this emotion rather than some other is an empirical question
Mozart B minor adagio extremely moving … why? that’s an empirical question (great composers have a good intuition for this).
Great music critics are able to pick out and articulate these - after hearing this it changes how you perceive the music.
Example: end of schubert piece “you can hear the body slipping into the water”
How is this related to hearing a piece of music as a certain genre?
“Romantic music is very expressive”
Problems
Other music just ‘describes’ emotions rather than expresses them
Yet much medieval music also is clearly expressive.
Positive account of how to characterize romantic music
There are expressive actions
Not described in the thought/belief model where we do actions towards some end / for some benefit. E.g. jump for joy.
There are actions we perceive as expressive.
Romantic music is perceived as expressive, and breaking classical conventions in order to express this emotion.
Allows one to not purely be defined as breaking conventions (otherwise you’d include impressionism, etc.)
Impressionist music is not perceived as expressive action.
July 18, 2011.
What does “conversational context” mean?
The situation in which a discourse takes place. Not just surrounding material but also the attitudes of the speakers, their interests, the point of what they’re trying to say, etc.
E.g. “everyone has arrived” or “there’s no beer”
The context constrains “everyone who was invited” / “no beer in the fridge”
Can we make everything explicit?
To make things explicit you draw from the context you are in
It’s an illusion to think we can speak “purely”
It’s essential for us to draw on info that is salient to the person we talk to
A big question for theorists: how is what is said in a statement dependent on context?
Under what possible worlds / conditions is what you say true?
Information conveyed by a statement is the exclusion of possible worlds.
“The cup is on the table” rules out the set of worlds in which the cup is under the table, etc.
If the cup gets moved, the three people in the room know both that it was moved and that the three people all know this fact, so it can then be taken for granted / it becomes part of the context.
If I respond to “everyone’s here” with “really? the queen is here?” that means I have included a possible world that the speaker had already ruled out.
A defective / mismatched context
So the possible worlds are used in multiple places
I say “he is over there” and you need to know what possible worlds are available as context to know who I refer to (suppose it’s John), but also now that you know that it affects the meaning what I’m saying (it rules out worlds wheree John is somewhere else)
The information content of the sentence is not just contained in the sentence itself. We can’t just isolate the context-dependent components by picking out indexicals.
Set of problems in philosophy: “essentially indexical belief”
Know objective facts but can’t locate oneself w/r/t to those facts
“I know I’m here” but I don’t know where here is.
There are thoughts that we can only have using indexicals (meaning changes when substituted).
“Frege problems”
When the same thing is named in two different ways. E.g. Hespherus and Phosphorus.
It was an empirical discovery that these two names named the same thing. Knowing that fact changes the meanings of sentences, even without indexicals.
Science gives you language for talking about a way for talking about the world in a fairly objective way, but there are still named terms that get their reference via naming processes.
Worry about realism. Is there something anti-realist about this kind of contextualism?
We can talk about the world only by connecting ourselves to it.
That’s no threat to the fact we are stating objective truths/falsehoods.
We can distinguish between the possible worlds with our contexts and be objectively right or wrong.
Use case of contextualism
Contextual theories can be used to address skeptical claims (“to know” is context dependent)
In politically contested discourse, context can be deliberately exploited to manipulate / control the discourse.
Radical contextualism gives us a means of knowing how to gain clarification in these situations.
September 8, 2011.
What is altruism
“pure altruism” Help to someone else at some cost to self
(distinct from reciprocal altruism: done with expectation of return)
Is the tendency to behave altrusitically was evolved?
Other animals act in benefit for kin
E.g. bird lures predator away from nest to protect her offspring
We have genetic disposition to protect our genes (even if not done on conscious level)
Human altruism is also an effect that is amplified for kin
We have urge to protect an unknown child
Perhaps we are just pattern matching (consciously or unconsciously) off of our altruism for offspring.
You see a burning building and a person inside it
It’s your daughter - you rush in without thinking (and societally judged as moral behavior)
It’s your neighbor - you call the fire department (societally judged as moral behavior)
This is very distinct from Kantian moral behavior which would judge the scenarios as roughly equal.
(this is not a good model of how we actually behave)
Evidence that this behavior can be explained via evolution
Humans are evolved animals and thus behavior can often be successfully explained via evolutionary biology (human moral behavior no different in this regard)
However, altruistic behavior seems to be taught. Would this mean it’s not evolutionary?
There’s a learning component (like language, but we would never use the fact that it’s learned to argue that the capacity / faculty for it isn’t innate)
After all, different cultures have different moral systems
But there is extraordinary similarity among all cultures, indictative as a common starting point
E.g. Act to help your own kin
Similar to facial expressions corresponding to certain motions being similar across different cultures
The moral “grammar” is there from evolution but we have to learn the semantics of that grammar and how to apply the rules.
Example of what concretely do we have to learn to be altruistic?
We have to learn who are our kin?
We have to learn what is helpful vs harmful (e.g. that the doctor sticking needles in is not harming your child)
We have to learn to share as children (but children learn this remarkably easily)
Can human ethical behavior be justified by the fact it was evolved?
No. Actual human norms for moral discourse/justification are needed to justify actions morally
To say “I shot the intruder because I evolved to act that way” would not be a socially acceptable justification
Evolutionary theory is used to explain what those norms are. (E.g. “why is it that ‘I was doing it to be altruistic’ is successful in justifying behavior to other humans?)
Are morals all contingent based on the influence of evolution (rather than coming from pure reason)
“It’s just the type of people we are”
Used to justify thinking of the world in causal terms (Kant says we simply are not capable of doing otherwise)
Evolutionary biology gives explanation (ancestors who didn’t think tigers were causally connected would get eaten)
Likewise for altruism as a first principle, it can be justified by this line
Evolutionary theory provides further explanation of why that’s the case, arguments for how it increased fitness + heritability.
It’s not contingent if it is who we are / we have a certain nature
How to respond of general criticism of evolutionary psychology as not rigorous/testible?
In any scientific domain there will be theories that are adequately justified or not
Justified empirical support for things in the domain of evolutionary psychology
Instinctive behavior can be inherited
Ducks have instictive mating dances, breed ducks and get hybrid dances (no one teaching)
Developmental studies
Sequence of things learned are constant (e.g. in language we learn simple nouns first, then add X, Y, forming complex sentences, etc.
As a species we do well at altruism in small groups and get worse and worse as our groups which are large
That’s who we are. Should we go ‘beyond’ how we evolved to be better?
Treating kin well and more distant things worse is a constant from who we are.
We severely mistreat others when we treat the other tribal group as “the other”/“not us”/inhuman.
We become better behaved when we use our cultural knowledge / rational faculties to see that the other tribe isn’t so different from us after all.
April 9, 2012
Moral realism - moral claims are objectively true or false
Morals are objects of belief (things out there)
E.g. courage is a virtue / justice is a virtue
Moral disagreement is possible between individuals and across cultures (no moral relativism in that sense)
Question KS is interested:
what are the implications of moral reason
But moral disagreement makes people think moral realism is false.
If it were true, then we’d converge on the truth like science.
But it’s unclear why one would think moral facts would make people converge on a solution.
Also historically, we had long periods of time where you’d look back and not see convergence (e.g. whether world was flat or not). By analogy, perhaps we are doing that with in morality.
It’s rather about how we can be justified to believe moral truths that would make you expect
But moral disagreements persist.
Even if we imagined knowing all the possible ‘scientific facts’
Sidestep with two moves
Shift from disagreements about morality to ethics (more broad: like “how to live”)
There are cases of philosophers who’ve held diametrically opposed views for millennia
E.g. Selfishness vs altruism
“If your views are true and confront with others who views are false, you should stick to your guns.”
In discussions of disagreement, we have a view “the equal weight view”
You should give others’ views equal weight to your own without a prior reason to discount their beliefs
Leads to skepticism.
But it’s not plausible because (argument of Tom Kelly)
It has you reason as if your only prior is how much you were likely to be right.
Nonmoral example:
weather prediction example
Equal weight view IS reasonable for perceptual experiences (this is where it gets its power from). The problem is philosophers who liken moral intuitions to perceptual appearances.
What is the alternative in the non-perceptual cases
Problematic alternative:
Keep the belief that moral beliefs bottom out in perceptual intuitions.
But relativize people’s intuitions (break asymmetry by saying opponent has bad intuitions or that morality’s purpose is to provide coherence of just your beliefs)
However, this is epistemic egoism.
Better alternative:
There is an asymmetry in the standard of justification of moral beliefs: true beliefs have better evidence for them.
Coherentists/reflective equilibrium etc. want to find a standard of justification that is independent of taking a stance on particular moral beliefs.
???
Knowing all nonmoral facts doesn’t help you resolve moral facts.
March 28, 2013.
Conflict between epistemic and objective notions of probability
In the former, to express a claim about a coin toss having a 50% chance of being heads is to make a claim about a rational being’s own knowledge, among other things.
Intuitively, we’d prefer to just say probability is a fact in the world, about a given chance mechanism.
However, we often harbor metaphysical notions of determinism: i.e. with full information before the toss (placement of coin in the hand, facts about the coin-tossers brain, etc.), we could deduce the outcome of the toss.
This makes us believe that, objectively, the coin toss result being heads is either 0 or 1. In general, there would be no non-extreme probabilities, which is at odds with what makes probability theory useful.
Therefore, the desire to not step on determinism’s toes historically has led to a dominance of epistemic notions of probability.
Why not just submit to epistemic notion?
it would be remarkable if the ordinary claim that a coin toss is fair were covertly a commentary on one’s own ignorance.
analogy: whether or not we are justified in believing something depends on our epistemic relation to the world. However, this doesn’t mean that the content of all our beliefs makes reference to our epistemic state.
But still, we then have to explain how to reconcile objective probability with determinism.
Conflict between determinism and objective probability is an illusion due to a misconception about the content of judgments of probability. The misconception:
Judgments of deduction viewed as just an extreme judgment of probability (where deduced judgments have probability 1).
All beliefs have an associated credence and full belief is merely a special case when that value is 1.
Example: “all balls in the urn are black, draw a ball, that ball will be black” is just a special case with p=1 in “fraction p of the balls in the urn are black, draw a ball, it has probability p of being black”
The 10-coin toss example below will show why the former is not special case of the latter, as the latter has a certain ambiguity.
Unambiguous statement “10 coins are drawn, 5 of which are heads”
If asked to compute the probability of it, we can do a calculation, but we’re implicitly assuming some extra structure because the question is ambiguous.
You get a different answer if we are informed the 10 coin tosses arose in the context of a different experiment: “toss the coin repeatedly until you get 5 heads in a row”.
Before we assumed the experiment was that the coin would be tossed 10 times and then experiment would stop. This is just a different modal assumption, but both interpretations are consistent with the factual statement in the problem.
We can’t asses probability of a proposition until we embed it in a modal structure.
The content of probability judgments are not propositional contents, but rather propositions embedded in some procedural context.
They are not the types of things we can arrive at by deduction.
Thus, probabilitic reasoning and deduction are distinct modes of inference.
Observing the coin is heads after the fact is no argument against the purportedly probabilistic nature of the coin toss.
The reason why it’s not a good idea to bet against Laplace’s Demon is not because the world has only objectively only extremal probability, but because the demon is not using probabilistic reasoning at all (he might as well be looking at the coin after the fact - he doesn’t have to asses s probabilities at all).
Like playing poker against an opponent with x-ray vision should not make us believe objective probability does not exist.
Upshots
Theoretical study of objective probabilities is back on the table.
relationship between inductive and deductive logic
E.g. carnap’s inductive logics have a language with play a role of setting up a procedural context in which it makes sense to ask for probabilities.
Language does not take such a role in deductive contexts.
E.g. a first order logic / deductive languages. If we make elementary statements more specific, the deductive relations will not change, but in an inductive language the probabilities may change dramatically.
What sentences to pick as elementary or basic is more important in an inductive language
What was wrong with classical behaviorism, from a conceptual point of view, is we can see it with the wisdom of hindsight is just a larval stage on the way to functionalism. As all of the considerations that lead people to think have direct stimulus response connections, are satisfied still, if you allow intervening states. It’s still an empirical undertaking, and so on. But there’s a lot more formal power, you can get Turing machines, if you can get functional states, so you can get a lot farther. That’s why nobody should be a classical behaviorist anymore: be a functionalist, you get all the advantages, and a lot more expressive power.↩︎
Hegel was the ‘Great Bad’ of Anglophone philosophy↩︎
i.e. practice relating to concepts.↩︎
This point is shared by the later Wittgenstein. The \(\ref{childrens_game|puzzles|reference}\) that Wittgenstein offers us (along the way to trying to dissolve the presuppositions that make it puzzling) center around the normative significance of beliefs/desires/intentions.↩︎
However, Sellars doesn’t extrapolate from this that logic is an optional superstructure in our lives - we need to be able to think and talk about the goodness of inferences.↩︎
in the narrow sense↩︎
We cannot deny there is any descriptive content due to \(\ref{frege_geach|Frege-Geach argument|related to Sellars}\)↩︎
i.e. material incompatibility↩︎
i.e. material consequence↩︎
Brandom says this is expressed, beginning in the section on Perception of [16]↩︎
not just metaphysically possible world, whatever that is↩︎
this characterizes the pre-Kantian tradition↩︎
A 85-7 / B 117-9 [19]↩︎
redness, lionhood↩︎
The words priori and posteriori literally make the order clear.↩︎